Augustine
Augustine
Gerard O’Daly
1
LIFE AND PHILOSOPHICAL READINGS
Augustine was born in Thagaste (modern Souk Ahras in Algeria) in Roman
North Africa in AD 354. He died as bishop of Hippo (now Annaba,
Algeria) in 430. His education followed the standard Roman practice of
the later Empire (Marrou [12.59]), in schools at Thagaste, Madauros, and
Carthage, and it involved some study of philosophical texts, if only for
their literary and rhetorical qualities. At the age of 18 he read Cicero’s
Hortensius as part of the syllabus at Carthage, and it affected him
profoundly, introducing him to philosophy, and in particular to ethical
eudemonism (conf. 3.7). He cites the Hortensius regularly in his writings.<sup>1</sup>
But, although already a Christian catechumen (his mother Monnica was a
pious believer), and inclined to think of Christ when ‘wisdom’ (sapientia)
was spoken of, he found himself more attracted to the Manichees than to
what he perceived as the crudities of style in the Latin translations of the
Christian scriptures available to him. What attracted him to Manichaeism
was its appeal to reason rather than authority (a polarity that was to
dominate his mature thought: see section 3): to the modern reader
confronted with the bizarre cosmic mythology of the Manichees, this seems
an odd claim. But the Manichees proffered a universal system,
encompassing cosmology, psychology, and a synthesis of several religions,
including Christianity; and they prescribed a way of life consistent with
their revealed ‘knowledge’. Augustine was to be deeply influenced by their
account of evil, based on the belief in an evil principle in the universe and
in humans, a ‘substance’ at war with the good principle in the individual
and the universe (duab. an.). It was many years before he shed this belief.
Furthermore, Manichaean criticism of the Old Testament enabled him to
reject what he took to be its primitive concept of God and its moral
ambiguities.
As a young man at Carthage Augustine read Aristotle’s Categories and
claims not to have found them difficult (conf. 4.28). His other early
philosophical readings are not easy to determine. Cicero, especially the
Tusculan Disputations, the De re publica, the De natura, deorum, and the
Academica (and to a lesser extent the De fato and the De officiis), is his
principal source of information about every period of Greek philosophy (he
probably read Plato’s Timaeus in Cicero’s translation).<sup>2</sup> In his first
published work, De pulchro et apto (not extant), on aesthetics, written in
380–1, Augustine reveals knowledge of the distinction between beauty
(kalon) and ‘appropriateness’ (prepon), the Stoic theory of beauty as
proportion of the parts of a thing, and the monad/dyad principles (conf. 4.
20–1),
Augustine adopted the career of a rhetor, teaching at Carthage, Rome
(from 383), and Milan (from 384), where he held the post of public orator
(Milan was then the seat of the Western imperial court). At Milan (possibly
in a Platonist circle including figures like the retired high public official
Manlius Theodorus) he encountered Neoplatonism, reading—in the Latin
translation by Marius Victorinus—works, probably by both Plotinus and
Porphyry, in 386 (conf. 7.13–27; beata v. 4; c. Acad. 3.41).<sup>3</sup> His
knowledge of Greek was mediocre. He expresses distaste for the way in
which it was taught at school (conf. 1.23), and he was always to be
dependent upon translations for his access to Greek philosophy, Scripture,
and theological literature.<sup>4</sup> At Milan he also heard the sermons of
Ambrose, whose Platonizing Christianity undermined the materialistic
concept of God that Augustine found in both Manichaeism and Stoicism,
and who initiated him into the subtleties of exegetical method, based upon
the distinction, taken from Philo of Alexandria and Greek Christian
theologians such as Origen, between literal and figurative readings of
Scripture. He underwent a conversion experience in autumn 386, resigning
his post at Milan and spending the winter of 386–7 in retreat at a country
villa in nearby Cassiciacum.
From this period came his first extant works, a series of philosophical
dialogues whose form is much influenced by Cicero, which includes the
Contra Academicos, a critique of Academic scepticism (Cicero’s Academica
is Augustine’s principal source), and, in the De ordine and the De beata
vita, discussions of the nature of happiness and its relation to knowledge,
God’s nature, order in the universe, and the problem of evil. In another
‘inner’ dialogue between Augustine and reason, the Soliloquia, he explores
the nature of mind, the identification of truth with being, and the problem
of error. Neoplatonist influences permeate these dialogues. Augustine’s
characteristic theories of the will and semantics were not developed until
after his baptism in 387 and his return to Thagaste in 388 (De libero
arbitrio, De Magistro). Anti-Manichaean polemic dominated his writings
at this time. The first mature synthesis of his thought, De vera religione,
was written in 390.
From 371 to 386 Augustine had lived with a concubine: the couple had a
son, Adeodatus, who stayed with Augustine after his mother was sent back
to Africa in 386, at a time when Augustine was planning to marry an
heiress of high social standing (Adeodatus died young, probably in 389).
Augustine’s conversion led to the abandonment of his marriage plans and
the adoption of a life of celibacy. At Thagaste he established a religious
community. In 391 he was ordained priest at Hippo, becoming bishop in
396. Several of his works at this time reveal the influence of Pauline
theology upon his thought. When he wrote his autobiography, the
Confessions, from 397 on, he was able to apply his analysis of the will and
Pauline principles to his conversion experience of 386: both elements were
missing from the Cassiciacum dialogues.<sup>5</sup>
By 397 Augustine’s philosophical views were largely formed, and there is
no new encounter with other thinkers or fresh ideas in his later career. But
he elaborated his thought in several major works, all written over several
years: the De trinitate (whose psychological schemes reveal much of his
philosophy of mind), the De Genesi ad litteram (on creation, the soul,
sense-perception, and imagination), the De doctrina christiana (on
hermeneutics), and the De civitate dei (on ethics and social theory). In the
last two decades of his life he wrote much on free will, grace, and the
causes of evil, in a series of polemical works directed against Pelagius and
his followers, in particular Julian of Eclanum.
Augustine’s philosophical readings were eclectic and haphazard. Only
Cicero was studied systematically, as part of an educational syllabus. Plato
was read either in translation or in extracts (or both), the Neoplatonists
likewise. The Middle Platonists were known indirectly, through the
doxographical tradition (Solignac [12.61]): Apuleius was an exception, but
was chiefly exploited for his demonology. Christian writers were more
often targets of criticism than sources of new ideas: Tertullian’s
corporealist views on the soul, and Origen’s theories of the soul’s preexistence,
periodic reincarnation, and embodiment as punishment for
previously committed sin, all invited Augustinian objections. But Augustine
made a lot of his limited philosophical background, exploiting it with
acuity and imagination.
2
AUGUSTINE’S CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY
Augustine philosophizes throughout his writings. But, despite the fact that
some of his earlier works concentrate on specific philosophical themes, the
great majority of his writings are responses to a variety of personal,
theological, and church political circumstances (Bonner [12.32]).
Speculation for its own sake, although it may determine the amount of
space that he devotes to analysing particular problems, is never what
motivates Augustine to write in the first place. The polemical aspect cannot
be neglected. The De libero arbitrio is directed against the Manichees, for
example (retr. 1.9). In longer works, such as De Genesi ad litteram, which
were not composed under pressure of time and whose subject-matter
offered scope for open exploration of certain (for example cosmological)
questions, Augustine speculates most freely (Gn. litt. 1.18.37–21.41; 2.9.
20–1; 2.18.38). Augustine does not construct a philosophical system. But
certain themes preoccupy him, and his treatment of them evinces a
continuity of development or a coherence of treatment that allows us to
describe his position with some confidence. At times he understands by
‘philosophy’ the Graeco-Roman tradition of rational inquiry, as opposed to
Christianity; and he distinguishes between rational method in philosophy
and Christian belief in religious principles that are often historical events
(above all, Christ’s Incarnation) (beata v. 4; c. Acad. 3.37–42; vera. rel. 2–
8, 30–3; conf. 7.13–27; civ. 8.1–12). He deprecates pagan philosophy,
when he wishes to throw Christian doctrine into sharp relief. At other
times, however, he does not distinguish between the philosophical and
theological aspects of his thought. Christianity is the ‘one true philosophy’
(c. Iul. 4.72), and the ‘true religion’ of De vera religione is inconceivable
without its Platonist components. Thus he can speak of a ‘Christian
philosophy’ (c. Iul. 4.72; c. Iul. imp. 2.166), arguing that the love of
wisdom, the search for, and discovery of, truth, and the quest for
happiness all find fulfilment in the Christian religion. Augustine
appropriates traditional philosophical questions, but the answers which he
provides are religious ones. Thus the universal desire for happiness, which
he grants to be the proper activity of the highest human faculty, the mind,
is, he argues, only fully satisfied in the afterlife, and not in a disembodied
mental state, but in the resurrected heavenly body of the saints.<sup>6</sup> At the
same time, the questions which he asks are those of the Greek and Roman
philosophical tradition. When he investigates problems of the soul, he
inquires into its origin or source, its substance, the nature of the body-soul
relationship, its immortality, its condition after death, and so on.<sup>7</sup> He does
not pretend to answer all questions: for example, when human souls are
created (see section 7).
The scope of Augustine’s Christian philosophy may be appreciated when
we realize that he fuses the ‘wisdom’ of the Hortensius with the ‘intellect’ of
the Neoplatonist writings and the ‘word’ of the beginning of John’s gospel
(conf. 3.7–8; 7.13–27; civ. 10.29). He establishes several parallels between
the themes of the Johannine prologue and Neoplatonist writings. Platonism
enjoys a special status in his thought. ‘If Plato were alive’ (vera rel. 3), he
would recognize in Christianity the realization of his striving: a
monotheistic religion with a belief in immaterial principles, God, and the
soul. But, despite its theoretical monism, Platonism is, Augustine believes,
vitiated by polytheistic demonologies (civ. 8–10).
Augustine’s familiarity with the doxographical tradition means that he
follows the school division of philosophy into three areas of physics,
ethics, and logic (vera rel. 30–3; civ. 8.4; ep. 118.16–21). But he employs
no such division in any stringent sense in his discussion of philosophical
issues. It serves chiefly to articulate his reporting of philosophical
doctrines, as well as to assess the achievement of Platonism in fusing
Pythagorean physics with Socratic ethics, and completing the fusion by the
development of dialectic (c Acad. 3.37; civ. 8.4).
Augustine embraces the traditional definition of philosophy as the
science of things divine and human, and he sometimes distinguishes
between sapientia as knowledge of things divine (including truth in the
strict sense), and scientia as the knowledge of temporal things (trin. 14.2–
3). He understands it to be the achievement of Christianity to establish the
true relationship between eternal immutable truth and the beliefs that we
may have about temporal things. The proportion of Timaeus 290 (being:
becoming : : truth: belief) expresses an ontological and epistemological
classification that Augustine approves (trin. 4.24). But he believes that the
links between the temporal and the eternal are only realized in the
incarnate Christ, who is both sapientia and scientia, and in the doctrines
which emerge in Christianity (Gn. litt. 1.21.41).
Augustine knows the term theologia from Varro’s scheme of the three
kinds of ‘theology’—mythical, natural, and civil—but he uses the word to
refer to Christian doctrine only once (civ. 6.8) and in passing. Nor does he
proffer a natural theology in the sense in which this is understood in
medieval and modern contexts, namely, a theology that refuses to admit
doctrinal propositions that are not also accessible to reason as premises. But
he is arguably the founder in the Western tradition of ‘philosophical
theology’, which does accept such doctrinal premises as assumptions,
testing their coherence by analysis and argumentation, explaining them and
analysing their implications and connections. Augustine’s programme aims
at illuminating faith, which is based on authority, by the understanding
which reason provides, inasmuch as this is possible. Nor is this attempt at
rational inquiry merely something in which Christians may indulge, but it
is a duty incumbent upon them, for it involves use of their God-given
reason, the same reason which enables them to believe in the first place
(ep. 120.3). Augustine interprets the Latin translation of the Septuagint
version of Isaiah 7:9 (‘Unless you believe, you shall not understand’) as an
assertion of temporal conditionality (faith precedes understanding), as well
as of confidence that ‘God will aid us and make us understand what we
believe’ (lib. arb. 1.4; 2.6). But if ‘authority is temporally prior, reason is
prior in reality’ (ord. 2.26). Augustine argues that even if Christian beliefs
are initially credible only because the believer subjectively accepts divine
authority, these beliefs are in principle accessible to, and explicable by,
rational inquiry. And he attempts to broaden the basis of authority,
stressing, for example, the role of historical evidence and wide acceptability
in the tradition of Christ’s life and teaching. His stand is in sharp contrast
to Tertullian’s anti-intellectualism, which uses the argument that the
mysteries of faith are inaccessible to reason, and that their very
inaccessibility constitutes their status as mysteries (De carne Christi 5.4; De
praescriptione haereticorum 7.2–3). Augustine appears to claim that all
mysteries may be understood, if not in this life, then in the afterlife. And
some, such as the Trinity, may only be partly understood (ep. 120.2).
Augustine’s claim, he assumes, is strengthened by his observation that the
same reason is operative in belief and in understanding.<sup>8</sup>
3
BELIEF AND KNOWLEDGE
Although he sometimes distinguishes sharply between the certainty of
knowledge and the insubstantial nature of belief (c. Acad. 3.37, 43; div,
qu. 9, 48; ep. 147.7, 10), Augustine, not least because of his Christianity,
more often grants belief, if properly founded, the status of a kind of
knowledge. If believing is nothing other than ‘thinking with assent’ (praed.
sanct. 5), belief is rational. The validity of our beliefs depends upon the
authority by which they are held, the evidence or testimony which
commands assent (c. Acad. 3.42–3; ord. 2.26–7; lib. arb. 2.5; util. cred.).
Different kinds of authority are in play in, for example, historical evidence
and the truths of religion, but it is the same kind of mental activity which
engages in belief in each case. Yet the objects of belief may differ radically.
Historical evidence can only be believed: it can never be scientific
knowledge (mag, 37; div. qu. 48). But religious truths may one day be
understood, and so known, by believers. In fact, the progression from
belief to understanding is a fundamental tenet of Augustine’s views about
our knowledge of truths about God, though the transformation of this kind
of belief into knowledge will, he argues, occur only in the afterlife (trin. 9.1;
ser. 43; en. Ps. 118, ser. 18.3). This theological postulate betrays a
fundamental attitude of Augustine’s, that belief is inferior to understanding.
True belief may be rational, justified, and trustworthy, but it lacks the firsthand
justification of knowledge, and the comprehensive synoptic overview
of a complex field achieved by understanding (mag. 31, 39–40, 46; ep. 147.
21; Burnyeat [12.67]). It also lacks the first-hand justification of senseperception:
properly authenticated sense-perception is a form of knowledge
(ep. 147.38; trin. 12.3; retr. 1.14.3) in the sense that historical testimony
never can be. It is only when Augustine is arguing against sceptics that he is
moved to talk of our ‘knowing’ historical facts (trin. 4.21; 15.21).
Augustine’s knowledge of Academic scepticism is chiefly informed by
Cicero’s Academica, and it was his disenchantment with Manichaeism that
made him a temporary sceptic (conf. 5.19, 25). His arguments against
sceptics in Contra Academicos are concerned with exposing inconsistencies
and inadequacies in the Academic position (such as the concept of the
‘persuasive’ or ‘probable’, and the claim that there can be an Academic
sage (c. Acad. 2.12, 19; 3.30–2)), and preparing the ground for an
acceptance of the possibility of epistemic certainty in general.<sup>9</sup>
Augustine’s premise that the sage alone is happy is tested by the sceptical
argument that wisdom may be the quest for truth rather than its
attainment. In his answer he argues that nobody can be happy if she
cannot attain something which she desires greatly, such as the truth (c.
Acad. 1.9). But this argument presupposes that happiness entails
accomplishment of desired goals rather than the conviction that the pursuit
of a worthwhile desire, even if unfulfilled, is satisfying (Kirwan [12.42] 17–
20). In fact, Augustine never repudiates the premise that the unremitting
search for truth may in itself be a worthy human activity, and that wisdom
may consist in the path that leads towards truth and not merely the goal of
truth discovered (c. Acad. 1.13–14).
The Academic claims that things may be credible or probable without
those or other things being known. Augustine exploits the fact that Cicero
translates the Greek term pithanon (‘persuasive’ or ‘credible’) by verisimile,
‘like truth’ (c. Acad. 2.16, 19, 27–8). Augustine argues that it is absurd to
claim that something is like a truth when one purports not to know what
the truth is, applying a version of Plato’s thesis (Phaedo 74d–e) that
comparing x with y entails previous knowledge of y. But I can say that x is
like y if I know how y would seem if it existed. The Academic claim stands
if the Academic knows ‘how a truth would seem if there were any’.<sup>10</sup>
Augustine’s argument fails.
Augustine’s critique of sceptical epochê or suspension of judgement—
itself an intended safeguard against the risk of error—concentrates on the
inevitability of risking error if one habitually assents to what one does not
know (c. Acad. 2.11). This is a neat rejoinder. Since action and the forming
of judgements are not to be avoided, as the Academic concedes, the
Academic cannot claim that suspension of judgement is either possible or
brings with it avoidance of error (c. Acad. 3. 33–6).<sup>11</sup>
Augustine’s attack on scepticism takes the form of a defence of the Stoic
criterion of truth (c. Acad. 2.11; 3.18, 21; cf. Cicero, Academica priora 18,
113). He believes that the evidence of sense-perception does not, strictly
speaking, satisfy the conditions of the criterion. His search for propositions
which satisfy the conditions, as he understands them, leads him to look for
propositions of such a kind that they cannot be taken for false. He argues
that propositions of logic (such as ‘not p and q’, ‘if p, then not q’) satisfy
the conditions, as do mathematical propositions (c. Acad. 3.21, 23, 25, 29;
cf. doctr. chr. 2.49–53). So do such propositions as ‘I exist’, ‘I am alive’, or
even ‘If I am deceived, I exist’ (beata, v. 7; sol. 2.1; lib. arb. 2.7; vera rel.
73; trin. 10.14; civ. 11–26). It is arguable that propositions of this last kind
are intended to demonstrate the impossibility of thinking of any kind
without existing, and that Augustine is inferring the certainty of our
existence from the fact of consciousness. But it may be that Augustine is
arguing that he cannot mistakenly believe that he exists, or is alive, etc.<sup>12</sup>
Does Augustine anticipate Descartes’s cogito? When Descartes’s first
readers suggested to him that this was so, Descartes replied that there was
a difference between Augustine’s use of the argument and his own.<sup>13</sup> But in
fact Augustine puts his cogito argument to various uses, to argue for the
immateriality of the mind, or as part of a demonstration of God’s existence.
In his account of what we can indubitably know Augustine follows the
Platonist tradition in asserting that knowledge is not derived from senseperception
or experience, but that truths are somehow impressed upon our
minds a priori. What are these truths? They certainly include the
mathematical and logical propositions alluded to above. But they also
include ideas or concepts like that of ‘unity’ (lib. arb. 2.21–3, 26, 28–9, 40;
trin. 8.4). For knowledge is not just of propositions; it is also direct
acquaintance with entities that correspond to the Forms of Plato and the
Platonist tradition, in which particular things in our world participate (div.
qu. 46). Augustine contrasts the immutability of the eternal Forms with the
mutability even of the human reason which apprehends them (imm. an. 7;
ser. 241.2). He adopts the Middle Platonist view that the Forms are the
thoughts of God, who looks into his mind in order to create the universe (div.
qu. 46; civ. 12.27). In Christian terms, Augustine links the concept of the
Forms to the belief that the son of God is both wisdom and ‘word’, in the
sense of a causal creative power (vera rel. 66, 113; ep. 14.4; civ. 9.22; Gn.
litt 1.18.36).
Augustine considers but rejects the Platonic doctrine of anamnêsis as an
explanation of the presence in the human mind of knowledge that is not
derived from sense-experience. Knowledge is recollection, an exercise of the
memory, but in the sense that when I know I actualize what is latent in my
mind, eliciting truths by a process of concentration. This sounds Plotinian,
but it is combined with a reluctance to believe in the pre-existence of the
soul (c. Acad. 1.22; sol. 2.35; imm. an. 6; ep. 7; conf. 10.16–19).<sup>14</sup> Nor is
the human mind able to realize knowledge unaided. Augustine believes that
divine illumination is required to achieve this. God is the light of the mind,
and knowing is a kind of mental seeing. The divine light illumines not
merely what is apprehended, but also the apprehending mind. Moreover,
the light of truth is also the light in which we make judgements, whether
about intelligible phenomena or sense-perceptions. But illumination’s role
is not just normative or formal: illumination attempts to account for the
mind’s access to concepts and ideas, not merely its power to judge (sol. 1.
12, 15; ep. 120.10; conf. 9.10; div. qu. 46; trin. 4.4; 14.21; Gn. litt. 12.31.
59).<sup>15</sup> Although it is obvious that the illumination theory is an aspect of the
doctrine of divine grace, it is not an attempt to deny the mind its proper
cognitive activity. Rather, it is a realization of the mind’s natural capacity.
Knowledge of this kind is a result of introspection. Augustine powerfully
reiterates the Neoplatonist themes of conversion or return to oneself, of
self-knowledge as the means to all knowledge, the fulfilment of a deep
desire to possess wisdom, as deep as the desire to be happy (vera rel. 72;
sol. 2.1; trin. 9.14; 10.1–16).<sup>16</sup> Self-knowledge is a realization of self-love,
but self-love moves beyond itself to the knowledge of truth (beata v. 33, 35;
ord. 2.35; trin. 9.18). In a sense, God is the truth which I know. But God is
not the Forms. Transcending them, he is both known and unknowable,
‘touched’ rather than apprehended, a vision like our seeing the Forms, but
unlike our seeing them a vision that cannot be complete in our temporal
condition (conf. 9.24; 10.35–8; trin. 15.2; ser. 117.5).
4
SEMANTICS AND HERMENEUTICS
The most discussed aspect of Augustine’s philosophy of language in this
century is the account of language-acquisition criticized by Wittgenstein for
concentrating on words as names of objects and on ostensive definition as
the means by which words are understood (Philosophical Investigations 1–
3, 32, citing conf. 1.13). Wittgenstein’s critique is, at least in part,
misplaced. Whereas Augustine tends to insist that single words are names,
he does not regard ostensive definition as the sole or even principal way in
which understanding of language is achieved. For Augustine, language is a
system of signs conveyed in speech: every word signifies something. What
words signify is not immediately obvious. They convey thoughts from
speaker to hearer, but it is not clear whether Augustine maintains that they
signify those thoughts, or the objects of those thoughts, or both thoughts
and objects. Augustine adapts to an explicitly linguistic context Stoic
discussions (themselves indebted to Aristotle) of signs as a means of
inference in the acquisition of scientific knowledge.<sup>17</sup> Verbal signs refer to
something ‘beyond themselves’. But verbal signs are not the kind of sign
upon which Stoic theory concentrates: these Augustine calls ‘natural’,
whereas verbal signs are ‘given’ by a speaker to express something, to
provide evidence of, at the very least, mental contents (mag. 1–31; doctr.
chr. 1.2; 2.1–4; dial. 5; conf. 1.7, 12–13, 23).
If verbal signs are evidential, they will signify not merely specific things,
but also facts, actual or purported. Thus sentences as well as individual
words signify, and some individual words (conjunctions or prepositions,
for example) are more readily understood as signifiers when they are
considered as parts of a sentence or proposition. But Augustine also attempts
to show that all individual words are names, and that every word can be
used to refer to itself: every word is a sign inasmuch as it can be used to
bring itself to mind (this is how Augustine deals with words like ‘if’ and
‘because’) (mag. 3, 13–19).
In the De dialectica<sup>18</sup> Augustine distinguishes between words and what
is ‘sayable’ (dicibile), the conception of a word in the mind, what is
understood by a word, the mental perception of a word (dial. 5). This
account has something in common with the Stoic lekta doctrine. But
there are substantial differences between the two concepts. If lekta are the
incorporeal meanings of words, they are only ‘complete’ as the meanings of
completed sentences. Their principal function is to be true or false, and
their linguistic form is propositional. Parts of lekta are not meanings.
Augustine’s dicibile concept is underdeveloped. In part, it resembles his
concept of the inner word, the notion that thought is a kind of inner speech
in no particular language, but capable of being verbalized, even if, as in the
case of God’s word, it is not vocal (see section 9).<sup>19</sup> Language expresses the
speaker’s will, verbal signs signify states of mind (‘if’ indicates doubt,
‘nothing’ a perception that there is no object or real thing there (mag. 3, 19)).
We explain words by means of other words, using signs to signify other
signs (mag. 7–18). Likewise, gestures, whether mimic or not, function as
signs that make things known (mag. 4–6). But we can also make things
known by performance, for example of an action like walking, where no
signs are used (mag. 29). Signs point beyond themselves to that which they
signify, and cognition of what is signified is superior to perception of its
sign. Augustine suggests that this is so because the sign is functionally
dependent upon the thing signified, or is a means to an end, but he does
not resolve satisfactorily the question of value (mag. 24–8). Why are words
inferior to things?
The reason why Augustine raises the value-question may be that, despite
his initial thesis that language teaches something, Augustine eventually
adopts the position that nothing is learnt by means of signs (mag. 32–5).<sup>20</sup>
Rather, it is perceptions of things that teach us the meaning of signs like
words. Words do not convey their meaning unless we know that to which
they refer. More precisely, words have the function of calling to mind the
things of which they are signs (mag. 33). But ‘calling to mind’ or ‘making
known’ or ‘showing’ is not the same as ‘teaching’, and having something
‘made clear’ is not the same as ‘learning’ it (mag. 33–5). Knowledge is
direct acquaintance with what is known, signs have an instrumental
function, they serve to remind us of what we know. Augustine expresses
this theory in Christian terms by asserting that the one teacher is Christ,
the divine ‘inner teacher’, the wisdom whereby we know what we know
(mag. 2, 38–40, 46). But we only achieve knowledge because we teach
ourselves, through introspection: we are no passive recipients of that which
we learn. This Platonist position leads to the devaluation of signs in the
learning process. Their function is auxiliary. They may prompt the direct
acquaintance that is knowledge. And they also serve as vehicles for
communication of thoughts and ideas. When communication occurs,
something is indeed transferred from one mind to another, but once again
it is not a case of communication from an active sign-giver to a passive signrecipient.
Rather, what one mind has apprehended is apprehended through
the sign by another mind: it is simply another instance of cognition (mag.
39–46).
The focus of Augustine’s semantics is epistemological rather than
linguistic, although he has interesting observations to make about
language and meaning. The uses of his sign-theory in theological contexts,
such as its application to his views on non-literal, figurative meanings of
Scripture or to the Church’s sacraments, proved to be highly influential.<sup>21</sup>
Together with his North African contemporary Tyconius, Augustine,
especially in the De doctrina christiana, develops a hermeneutics of reading
Scripture that is profoundly original, with repercussions beyond Biblical
interpretation.
5
ETHICS, POLITICAL THEORY, AESTHETICS
Augustine appropriates the eudemonist ethics of ancient philosophy.<sup>22</sup>
Happiness (beatitudo) is a universal human desire (c. Acad. 1.5–9; beata v.
10, 14; civ. 10.1), the goal (finis) of human endeavour (civ. 19.1): it is the
highest good for humans (in one version of this thesis Augustine posits
peace, rather than happiness, as the universal goal (civ. 19.10–13). In
common with the eudemonistic tradition since Aristotle, Augustine
investigates what constitutes the well-being of the human being as a
rational being (beata v. 30–7; lib. arb. 2.7, 26; Gn. c. Man. 1.31). He does
not equate happiness with pleasure or enjoyment, any more than Aristotle
or the Stoics do, although he argues that the happiness appropriate to
humans, if realized, is accompanied by delight and enjoyment (doctr. chr. 1.
3–5; trin. 1 11.10). The happiest form of life is living in accordance with
reason, whether this consists in the search for truth or its discovery and
possession, the state of wisdom (sapientia) that reflects divine wisdom (see
section 3). The proper end or goal for humans is to ‘enjoy God’ qua truth
as an end in itself, and this teleological goal should also determine all our
moral choices (lib. arb. 2.35–6; civ. 8.8; 15.7; c. Faust. 22.78).
In one sense, Augustine’s account of happiness equates it with a form of
knowledge, namely knowledge of what is best and highest: happiness
consists in contemplation of stable eternal being, something that endures
and, unlike other kinds of possessions, cannot be lost (beata v. 11; lib. arb.
1.32–4; vera rel. 86; mor. 1.5). But Augustine qualifies this equation of
perfect virtue with knowledge by an insistence that enjoying or ‘possessing’
God entails doing what God wills, living well, performing virtuous actions.
On the one hand, therefore, wisdom is contrasted (Stoically) with folly
(beata v. 28–9). But Augustine also argues that being virtuous and its
contrary are not merely instances of knowledge or ignorance. In this
context his concepts of use and enjoyment, and his notion of the will, are
crucial.
The Augustinian contrast between use and enjoyment is influenced by
rhetorical and philosophical antitheses in Cicero, in particular the ‘usefulgood’
(utile-honestum) contrast (div. qu. 30). At first sight, however, it is
not so much a distinction between kinds of evaluation of temporal things
as a contrast between the eternal and the temporal (lib. arb. 1.32–4). In
order to enjoy God, who is eternal being, we may use temporal things, as
means to an end, in an instrumental way. Augustine includes other human
beings among the objects of use, but only by arguing that my use of them is
appropriate if it involves love of them ‘on God’s account’ (propter deum)
(doctr. chr. 1.3–4, 20–1).<sup>23</sup> In Augustine’s maturer thought the category of
use is not seen in exclusively instrumental terms, but as a pointer towards
the activity of willing, so that even enjoyment becomes a sub-category of
use. God’s love for us is not ‘enjoyment’, for that would imply that God
needs us for his blessedness. Divine love is rather ‘use’ in a providential
sense (doctr. chr. 1.34–5). If there is order and hierarchy among beings, it
is an ‘order of love’ (ordo amoris) (civ. 15.22). A difficulty with human
beings is that, whereas their relations with one another are temporal, they
are not just temporal beings. Augustine’s vision of the afterlife for those
saved is of a heavenly community of God and the saints: thus loving (or
enjoying) one another in God becomes a frequent expression in his
attempts to escape from problematic consequences of the application of the
use-enjoyment category to human relations (doctr. chr. 1.36–7; trin. 9.13).
Augustine appropriates the Greek philosophical principle that what is
especially valuable about truth and knowledge is that they cannot be lost
involuntarily (mor. 1.5). He understands the principle in terms of love,
rather than merely of choice (trin. 13.7–11). This is in part because, in
thinking about truth, he is thinking about a person, God, and our relation
to that person. But the principal reason why he talks of love in this context
is to be found in his psychology. It is commonplace in Augustine that what
I do depends upon what I love, not merely in the sense of what I value, but
above all in the sense that I act in accordance with a settled inclination
(conf. 13.10; civ. 14.7). Acting in accordance with a settled inclination is,
for him, acting voluntarily in the strict sense. He finds no place for the
Aristotelian view that enkrateia (self-mastery) may involve acting
voluntarily and morally despite inclining to the wrong things. For Augustine
it is not possible to love and value the wrong things and at the same time to
choose what is right (conf. 8.19–24). Loving the right things is a question of
character, not just of rational insight.<sup>24</sup>
Loving something is a necessary condition of willing it: sometimes
Augustine suggests that it is tantamount to willing it. Loving the right
things for the right reasons is a pre-condition of acting well. Loving the
wrong things, or the right things for the wrong reasons, leads to evil
actions. Reacting against the Manichaean belief that evil is a substance or a
nature in the universe and in ourselves, and also to some extent reacting
against the Plotinian view that metaphysical evil (matter or bodies formed
in matter) somehow helps to determine moral evil,<sup>25</sup> Augustine argues that
whatever exists is, qua created by God, good in some degree (civ. 19.13). If
things ceased to be good in any sense, they would cease to exist. On this
principle things are relatively evil to the degree that they lack goodness.
Evil is privation of good, but not in an absolute sense. This is not
necessarily a moral distinction: a stone has less goodness than a mind, but I
cannot speak of the stone’s moral status. Evil in the moral sense is,
Augustine suggests, the fact or consequence of willed evil action, chosen by
a mind (angelic or human) that remains essentially good, whose nature is
good (civ. 12.1–9). Persons are, strictly speaking, not evil: actions may be.
If love determines action and is a symptom of character, self-love is the
source of sin: more specifically, the source is pride, understood as a refusal
to accept subordination to God, to acquiesce in one’s place in the hierarchy
of beings. In Platonist terms, this is a ‘turning away’ from God to selfabsorption
(sibi placere), a failure to understand the relationship between
God and humans. Adam’s fall results from the delusion that he is an
autonomous being. His sin is a ‘perverse imitation of God’ (conf. 2.12–14;
civ. 12.6–8; 14.12–14).
Virtue is defined in terms of order (doctr. chr. 1.28; civ. 15.22). In the early
De beata vita, Augustine understands the virtues to possess a kind of
measure that is without either excess or defect (beata v. 30–3). In that work
he suggests that the attainment of wisdom by the sage entails possession of
the virtues. In his later writings he is less sanguine about the perfectibility of
human nature in this life. Life is a continuing struggle with vices; virtue is
not a stable, attainable state (civ. 19.4). The virtues control but do not
extirpate emotions. Augustine recognizes the traditional four cardinal
virtues (mor. 1.25; div. qu. 31). Virtue is a form of love (mor. 1.25, 46),
primarily of God, but also of other humans. Justice is ‘giving God his due’
(civ. 19.21) as well as loving one’s neighbour. The practice of the virtues
expresses the inherently social nature of humans: we are naturally members
of societies (civ. 12.22; 19.12; ep. 130.13). Augustine subscribes to the
natural law theory (div. qu. 53; spir. et litt. 48). Our awareness of the
natural law derives from self-love, or the instinct for self-preservation, and
it extends (as does the Stoic concept from which it derives) to a realization
of the need for justly regulated relations with others (civ. 19.4; doctr. chr.
1.27). Primarily, this realization is a form of the Golden Rule<sup>26</sup> in its
negative version ‘Do not do to others what you would not have others do
to you’ (ep. 157.15; en. Ps. 57.1; Io. ev. tr. 49.12). Augustine gives the
natural, or, as he often calls it, eternal law the status of a Platonic Form
inasmuch as he says of it, as he says of the Forms, that it is ‘stamped on
our minds’ (lib. arb. 1.50–1; trin. 14.21; ser. 81.2). Strictly speaking, the
laws of human societies should be framed in accordance with divine
eternal law (vera rel. 58), but it is political authority, rather than strict
conformity to natural law, that gives validity to positive law (ep. 153.16;
civ. 19.14). Only those human laws that are explicit contraventions of
divine commands may be disobeyed, and Augustine’s understanding of
what constitutes divine commands is specific: they are commands directly
revealed in Scripture, such as the prohibition of idolatry (doctr. chr. 2.40,
58; civ. 19.17; ser 62.13). Augustine is otherwise reluctant to assert as a
principle that individuals may decide for themselves whether an individual
temporal law is just or unjust, even if promulgated by an unjust ruler or
without reference to the natural law. One obvious exception is a law that
might sanction something contrary to nature (Augustine’s example is
sodomy (conf. 3.15–16)). Other laws (for example, about monogamy or
polygamy) merely reflect the customs of different societies (conf. 3.12–13;
c. Faust. 22.47). Hence there is scope for great differences in the laws of
different societies.<sup>27</sup>
The peace which is the highest good is also the proper aim of human
societies. They should aspire to practise justice, to be stable, to be equitable
in their dealings.<sup>28</sup> In practice, this is often only realized by coercion,
punitive measures, and harsh exercise of authority: Augustine finds this
appropriate to our fallen human nature, vitiated as it is by original sin.
Controlling humans driven by greed, pride, ambition, and lust calls for a
rule of law that, at best, contains vestiges or traces of authentic justice
(Simpl. 1.2.16; trin. 14.22). Certain features of his society—private
property and slavery, for instance—Augustine regards as consequences of
the Fall, not, strictly speaking, natural, at least not natural to our pristine
created selves (civ. 19.15–16; Io. ev. tr. 6.25–6). In general, Augustine
insists that it is the proper use of wealth and possessions that counts. He
proffers no moral critique of the economic or social institutions of his
society. Misuse of wealth is wrongful possession of it, not in the legal sense
(unless the misuse is also criminal), but in the moral sense that, in strict
justice, the individual has forfeited his right to a material good (ep. 153.26;
ser. 113.4; en. Ps. 131.25). Renunciation of property and wealth is part of
the ascetic ideal, but it is the desire for unnecessary wealth, rather than the
possession of wealth, that is immoral. Curbing desires is a central function
of political authority, and it often has to take the form of merely restricting
the harm that those who misuse the world’s goods would do: Augustine
takes a sanguine view of government, which will not be required in the
ideal state of heaven, where the tranquillity of order that is only realized by
the rule of law in earthly societies (and only infrequently) will be realized
spontaneously by the community of saints (civ. 19.11, 13–14; 22.30).<sup>29</sup>
One social institution which Augustine defends is matrimony. His
defence argues that it is not merely for the procreation of children but also
to provide fellowship for the partners (b. coniug. 3). But a state of sexual
abstinence is preferable. Augustine’s one argument for this view revolves
around his understanding of sexual arousal. He has many grounds for
championing abstinence as the supreme form of ascetic renunciation,<sup>30</sup> but
they usually reflect his attitude to sensuality in general and control of
emotions in particular. The argument concerning sexual arousal is that it is
involuntary, not subject to the will or consent (civ. 14.16, 24; ep. 184A.3).
It seems to be an exception to the rule that other bodily organs can be
activated by the will, with or without emotional stimulus, indeed require
some kind of willing in order to operate. But sexual arousal happens
without the will’s consent, and neither can it be aroused at will. Even when
desire has fired the mind after arousal (and so some kind of willing has
occurred), the sex organs may fail to be responsive. Augustine considers
this to be a consequence of original sin, and can envisage a pre-lapsarian
form of sexual activity that is controlled by the will. His Pelagian adversary
Julian of Eclanum argues that sexual desire is not merely necessary for
copulation but also natural and in itself morally neutral (c. Iul. imp. 1.70–
1; 3.209). But why are anarchic genitals so bad? What distinguishes sexual
arousal from, say, sneezing or coughing?
Augustine seems to argue that what distinguishes it is its power over
both body and mind: it overwhelms a person emotionally, physically, and
mentally. This he finds sinister. There is, by implication, no emotion which
cannot be brought under the control of reason, but sexual arousal is
impervious to reason and to will (civ. 14.16). Augustine’s other arguments
—such as the sense of shame attending sexual desire and acts—cannot
explain why sex is tainted. But he finds that sexual arousal occurs even in
the dreams of those who, like him, have devoted themselves to a life of
continence, and that in dreams he seems to consent to sexual acts that his
waking self repudiates. He argues that this cannot involve any moral
responsibility, but feels that such dreams are a symptom of his imperfect
moral status, as well as being yet another indication that the sex instinct is
beyond our conscious control (conf. 10. 41–2; Gn. litt. 12.15.31).<sup>31</sup>
In several areas of ethics where Augustine’s ideas are not necessarily
original he exerted, because of his authority and the wide dissemination of
his views, a considerable influence. This is the case with what he says
about the ethics of warfare, which does not advance much beyond Cicero
(civ. 1.21; 4.15; 19.7; ep. 189.6; 229.2; c. Faust. 22.75),<sup>32</sup> or his views
about suicide, which contain the arguments that we do not dispose of our
lives (a Platonic argument) and that killing oneself is a kind of cowardice
and of despair, the triumph of emotion over reason (civ. 1.17–27; ser. 353.
8).<sup>33</sup>
Augustine’s Platonism makes him equate the beautiful with the good.
The God whom we love is the supreme beauty which we desire (conf. 7.7;
10.8, 38; sol. 1.22; trin. 1.31; civ. 8.6, 11.10; ser. 241.2; en. Ps. 44.3).
Beauty consists of a numerically founded form or relation whose sensible
manifestation is a reflection of a higher, immutable divine ‘reason’.
Beauty’s structure is rational and accessible to the judging mind (ord. 1.18,
2.33–4; mus. 6.30, 38; Gn. litt. 3.16.25). But the formal beauty of the arts
is to be transcended no less than natural beauty, and all perceptible beauty
is an ‘admonition’ to mind to ascend to a spiritual plane where intelligible
beauty is one with truth and wisdom (conf. 7.23; 10.9; vera rel. 101). In
his creation account, Augustine uses the craftsman-analogy: God is the true
artist and the universe is an artefact whose perfection is both numerical and
hierarchical (civ. 11.18, 21–2; 12.24–5; Gn. c. Man. 1.25). If we could
perceive the whole, we would realize that evil in the universe does not
detract from its overall goodness, and that the presence of antitheses and
contraries in it may enhance its beauty (ord. 1.18; conf. 7.18; civ. 11.18,
22; 12.4). Augustine recognizes the temptations inherent in aesthetic
pleasure, as in any pleasure. He perceives, for example, that piety and
fervour can be nourished by church music, but that the senses may
sometimes usurp the place of reason when we delight in song (conf. 10.49–
50). Once more, it is a question of proper use of a lesser good. To delight
in the beauty of the universe for its own sake, even if the delight is
intellectual rather than sensual, is to confuse reflected goodness and beauty
with the truly and perfectly good and beautiful. This would be a failure to
know the Good and to love God. It would also, Augustine believes, leave
us dissatisfied, our potential for the perfecting of our natures unrealized.<sup>34</sup>
6
THE WILL
Augustine’s concept of the will<sup>35</sup> and defence of free will rest on the
paradox that God determines our wills when we will the good, but that
such willing is nonetheless free choice, for which we are responsible. This
applies as much to Adam before the Fall as to humanity’s postlapsarian
state. Divine help for Adam in paradise was a necessary, but not sufficient
condition of his free choice of the good, and neither was freedom of choice
sufficient. Only divine grace and human free choice together are sufficient
for attaining the good (civ. 14.26; corrept. 28–34). Augustine argues,
puzzlingly, that Adam, and all created beings, have a tendency to choose evil
rather than good because they are created out of nothing and are possessed
of an ontological weakness that does not entail their sinning but makes it
possible that they will choose evil (civ. 12.6; 14.13; c. Iul. imp. 5.3).
In an early work, the De libero arbitrio, Augustine describes the faculty
of free will as a middle good whose activity is necessary to virtue: the
neutral will can be used either rightly or wrongly, it is morally indifferent
(lib. arb. 2.50–3). But as his thought develops, Augustine argues for the
concept of a will that is morally determined, that is good or evil depending
upon the value of what is willed. This is in part a reaction against Pelagian
views. Pelagius describes human choice as a ‘power to take either side’,
neither good nor evil per se: ‘in the middle’. Augustine denies that the same
will can choose good and evil. Will is either good or evil, or, more
accurately, the power of free choice (liberum arbitrium) of the will
(voluntas) may be exercised in a good or an evil way (lib. arb. 2.1). The
Pelagians had a strong case when they argued that Augustine’s views in De
libero arbitrio were akin to theirs (retr. 1.9; conf. 8.19–21; pecc. mer. 2.18–
30; spir. et litt. 58; gr. et pecc. or. 1.19–21).
Will for Augustine is a mental power or capacity, like memory, but
because it is morally qualified it reflects a person’s moral standing in a way
that memory cannot. As well as referring to a good or bad will in the
singular, Augustine talks of two or more wills in us, where there is moral
conflict: in this latter case, our wills are the range of possible courses of
action open to us (lib. arb. 2.51; conf. 8.19–21; gr. et lib. arb. 4).
If God determines my good will, how can I be free? Augustine believes
that the fact that God has foreknowledge of my will does not determine
that will, for God’s knowledge (strictly speaking, not foreknowledge) is
timelessly eternal (Simpl. 2.2.2; civ. 5.9; 11.21; praed. sanct. 19). Divine
omniscience is compatible with free choice of the will. Yet predestination to
salvation is actively caused by God. Augustine argues that this does not
make us passive recipients of divine grace. The notion of ‘compulsion of
the will’ is to him an absurd one (c. Iul. imp. 1.101; c. ep. Pel. 2.9–12).
Willing entails the power to do X through, and only through, the means of
willing X. Augustine’s psychology is based upon the belief (which he
derives from analysis of our behaviour) in the centrality of concentration
or attention (intentio) in all mental processes. The mind is activated by the
will, not in the sense of one faculty or ‘part of the soul’ affecting another,
but inasmuch as we cannot perceive, or imagine, or remember without
concentrating or paying attention or willing to do so. Thus grace may only
become operative in humans when the will is attracted to the good. For the
will is always goal-directed, and will entails assent. Willing is a form of
action, not a reaction to external stimuli (gr. et lib. arb. 32; c. ep. Pel. 1.5,
27). If divine grace is irresistible, this does not entail that grace compels us.
People are ‘acted upon that they may act’ (corrept. 4). It is seems
impossible to argue that this is not determinism. What Augustine is
stressing is that consent is necessary to the modus operandi of the will’s
reception of grace.
Augustine’s arguments against Pelagius’ description of human choice as
‘a power to take either side’ is based upon the observation that it posits the
same cause (the indifferent will) of opposite effects (gr. et pecc. or. 1.19–21).
Augustine appears here to reject the so-called ‘freedom of indifference’ of
the will. His position seems to be closer to freedom of spontaneity, where
absence of force or compulsion, rather than absence of external causation,
is characteristic. Will is not self-determining, yet humans are not accurately
to be described as being instruments of God’s will. Thus the Stoic example
of the dog tied to, and dragged by, the cart (SVF II 975 [7.2]) cannot apply
to Augustine’s understanding of spontaneity. Freedom is not merely
acquiescence in God’s activity, but rather the exercise of a human faculty
that involves both consent and power to act, or to initiate action. Both in
his account of Adam’s freedom in paradise and in his early version of his
freewill theory in De libero arbitrio Augustine subscribes to the liberty of
indifference account; but it is not applicable to fallen humanity. However,
the fallen human being possesses both the ability and, it may be, the
opportunity, to act otherwise, even though that ability is not, in fact,
exercised when the will is determined by the good. Exercising the ability to
commit sin is not, of course, an exercise of freedom of the will for the
mature Augustine. Rather, it is an instance of the enslavement of the will to
evil, from which only divine grace can liberate it. If freedom to sin is a form
of slavery, then willing and obedient slavery to the will of God is true
freedom (ench. 30). On the other hand, sin is the price of having free will,
and having free will is a necessary condition of acting rightly. Sin is the
price of freedom, because freedom entails absence of compulsion. This is
Augustine’s version of the free will defence (ench. 27; lib. arb. 2.1–3).<sup>36</sup> It
reveals why defence of free choice of the will seems to be so important to
Augustine. Heavenly rewards (and hellish punishments) make no sense if
they are not a consequence of acting rightly (or wrongly), even if God is the
author of our virtuous actions. The argument does not explain
satisfactorily why God tolerates sin. Augustine’s characteristic strategy here
is to concede that nothing happens ‘apart from God’s will’, even those
things, like sin, that happen ‘against God’s will’ (ench. 100). God lets us
sin, but does not cause us to do so. But it is difficult, on these premises, to
avoid the consequence that God is responsible for sin, in the sense that he
is responsible for states of affairs brought about voluntarily, if not
intentionally, by him. The distinction between causing and permitting seems
impossible to maintain.<sup>37</sup>
God’s grace precedes (in Augustine’s terminology) acts of the free will.
God makes good decisions possible, but also causes them, for grace is
irresistible. Prevenient grace is more than merely enabling, nor is it a form
of co-operation between God and humans. Rather it is operative. Again,
the question arises: can a decision caused by God be free? Augustine’s
answer is the one discussed above. God causes the reception of his gifts by
the mechanism of human consent. But since God’s will is never thwarted, it
is as true to say that what happens as a consequence of divine will happens
by necessity, as it is to maintain that human realization of good behaviour
is an instance of human freedom. ‘God cannot will in vain anything that he
has willed’ (ench. 103), and the human being whom God wills to save
cannot be damned. But neither will such a human being be saved against
her will.
7
SOUL
Augustine’s concept of soul as an immaterial, naturally good, active,
inextended, and indivisible substance owes much to his Neoplatonist
readings. It is also likely that Porphyry is a major source of his knowledge
of the contents of Plato’s Phaedo, Phaedrus, and Timaeus. Scripture and
the Christian tradition provide Augustine less with a concept of soul’s
nature than with texts requiring exegetical elucidation by means of
Platonist psychology, and attempts at philosophical exegesis which he
rejects, such as Tertullian’s corporealist theories and Origen’s arguments for
pre-existence, embodiment as punishment for sin, and reincarnation.<sup>38</sup>
Soul is the life-principle, and to various kinds of life—vegetative,
sentient, intelligent—correspond degrees of soul (civ. 7.23, 29; en. Ps. 137.
4). The awareness that we are alive is awareness that we are, or have,
souls: Augustine argues that we are empirically conscious of the fact that we
have a soul, even if we do not perceive soul with any of the senses (beata.
v. 7; trin. 8.9). The single soul in humans has rational and irrational
faculties: the latter include the powers of impulse, sense-perception, and
certain kinds of memory, and they can be disturbed by the passions. It is
the function of the rational soul (and mind is a part of soul) to control the
irrational element (civ. 5.11; 9.5; en. Ps. 145.5). There is an inescapable
moral dimension in Augustine’s accounts of the levels of soul, and it is
linked to the Neoplatonist concept of soul’s conversion to the Good, seen
in terms of an ascent from the corporeal and percipient levels, through
those of discursive reason and moral purification, to the intellection of the
highest principle by a mind that is morally and mentally prepared for
understanding. This conversion or return makes good the ‘turning-away’
from divine wisdom and interiority that characterizes sin: rejecting the
distracting multiplicity of what is external, it discovers the divine within us
(imm. an. 12, 19; ord. 1.3; 2.31; conf. 2.1; 7.23; 13.3; trin. 8.4; 10.7; 14.
21).
Soul, the principle of movement in bodies, is itself a self-moving
principle: my consciousness of my self-movement is my consciousness of
my power to will (div. qu. 8). Soul’s movement is not local, nor does it
entail substantial change, but impulse and will often result in bodily
movement (ep. 166.4; quant. an. 23). Rejecting all corporealist theories of
the soul’s substance, Augustine engages in polemic against them, be they
Epicurean, Stoic, Manichaean, or Christian. Examination of the nature of
soul’s activities rules out even the most subtle of corporeal soul-substances.
Memory and imagination are not subject to the physical law that corporeal
likenesses correspond in size to the bodies in which they are reflected, like
the image in the pupil of the eye. Perception, concentration, and volition
are indicators of immateriality, as is the mind’s power of abstraction and
intellection of non-corporeal objects, such as geometrical figures (quant. an.
8–22; Gn. litt. 7.14.20; 7.19.25–20.26). Although physical and mental
powers appear to develop concomitantly in growing humans, there is no
strict correlation between their development, still less any evidence that soul
physically grows or diminishes (quant. an. 26–40). Augustine is
nonetheless aware that it is paradoxical to maintain that soul is present as
an entirety throughout the body and is yet inextended and indivisible. It is
omnipresent not in a spatial sense, but as a ‘vital tension’ (vitalis intentio),
which, for example, enables it to perceive in more than one bodily part
simultaneously (imm. an. 25; quant. an. 26, 41–68; ep. 166.4).
Soul is mutable: that makes it substantially different from God’s
unchangeable nature (conf. 7.1–4). As a Manichee, Augustine had believed
that the good human soul is part of the divine, and he sees Stoic pantheism
as leading to the same conclusions (duab. an. 16; vera rel. 16; civ. 7.13,
23). The soul is subject to various kinds of mutability. Learning, the
affections, moral deterioration and progress, all effect changes in the soul
(imm. an. 7). Soul exists in a temporal medium in which it can and must
change. It is maintained in its continued existence by God’s will (div. qu.
19; ep. 166.3; trin, 4.5, 16, 24). To characterize soul’s changeability
Augustine uses the Aristotelian distinction between a subject and
qualitative changes in that subject which do not entail substantial change in
it (Aristotle, Categories 2). For the soul’s identity persists through change.
In fact, the necessarily unchangeable nature of certain kinds of knowledge
entails the substantial identity of the mind in which, as in a subject, such
knowledge is present. Augustine regards this as proof of the soul’s
immortality (imm. an. 5, 7–9; sol. 2.22, 24). He also argues for its
immortality from its equation with life. If being alive is the defining
characteristic of soul, soul cannot admit the contrary of life and so cannot
cease to live (imm. an. 4–5, 9, 12, 16; trin. 10.9): this is the final argument
for the soul’s immortality in Plato’s Phaedo (102a-107b). Augustine
believes that the irrational human soul is also immortal, and that we have
both memory and feelings in the afterlife (civ. 21.3; Gn. litt. 12.32.60–34.
67). The soul, like God inasmuch as it has a similar creative and rational
domination over subordinate creation, cannot, in its nature, be evil. It is a
corruptible good, occupying a medial position between God and bodies. Its
position on the scale of being and its moral standing should coincide.
Pride, a desire for self-mastery in an order where the soul is not the master,
degrades it morally to animal level (conf. 7.18; civ. 19.13; en. Ps. 145.5; ep.
140.3–4; trin. 12.16). But this degradation can only be understood in a
metaphorical sense. Augustine repudiates Manichaean and Platonist
doctrines of transmigration of human souls into, or from, animal bodies,
agreeing with what he takes to be Porphyry’s rejection of the view that a
rational soul, whose reason is not accidental but belongs to its substance,
could become the essentially different irrational soul of an animal, or vice
versa (civ. 10.29–30; 12.14, 21, 27; 13.19; Gn. litt, 7.10.15–11.17).
The incorporeal soul cannot be a condition of the body, such as its
harmony or the proportion of its parts (imm. an. 2, 17; Gn. litt. 3.16.25; 7.
19.25). Yet soul is entirely present in every part of the body, and its
various activities and conditions point to a symbiosis in which body and
soul influence one another (ep. 9.3–4). Soul is mixed with body in a way
that allows each element to maintain its identity, as in the mixture of light
and air (ep. 137.11; Gn. litt. 3.16.25). The ‘vital tension’ (ep. 166.4) by
which soul is present to body has also a volitional dimension (mus. 6.9; Gn.
litt. 8.21.42). Augustine is aware of the Platonist view that, even when not
embodied, souls may inhabit a vehicle, but doubts the truth of the theory,
considering pure spiritual existence to be possible, even if he also believes
in the future resurrection of the body: it is natural for souls to govern
bodies (ep. 13.2–4; Gn. litt. 8.25.47; 12.32.60; 12.35.68).
On two traditional problems Augustine remains agnostic: the origin of
souls, and the existence of a world-soul. On origins he vacillates between
the view that souls are propagated by parents, like bodies, and the theory
that they are created directly by God as each individual is conceived. The
former is difficult to explain, the latter seems to compromise the
completeness of God’s creation. Augustine considers various forms of preexistence
theory, including the view that all souls are created individually in
the moment of creation, and embodied at different times. But his
discussions remain inconclusive, just as he remains uncertain about the
moment when the foetus is animated (lib. arb. 3.56–9; Gn. litt. 6; 7; 10).<sup>39</sup>
Hevacillates on the question of the world-soul because he finds it plausible
to believe that the ordered and cohesive universe owes its continued
existence to the presence of a cosmic soul. He objects to particular
consequences of world-soul theories (dual good and evil cosmic principles,
as in Manichaeism; Stoic views on the world as the body of a divine mind)
rather than the theories as such, and is benevolent towards what he takes
to be Plotinus’ position, that cosmic soul is created and illuminated by a
transcendent divine principle. But his tentative conclusion is that the
universe is an inanimate body full of stratified soul-kinds (imm. an. 24; ord.
2.30; civ. 4.12, 31; 7.5–6, 23; 10.2, 29; 13.16–17).<sup>40</sup>
When Augustine analyses human behaviour, he recognizes that impulse
or assent (appetitus) is the cause of action, whether it is the impulse of selfpreservation,
or motions of appetency or avoidance or simply the motor of
a proposed course of behaviour (div. qu. 40; ep. 104.12; civ. 19.4; trin. 12.
3, 17). Augustine’s views on impulse and assent are crucial to his account of
the will. The links between impulse, assent, will, and desire are
fundamental in his psychology: to eradicate desire is impossible, and desire
can be for good things—knowledge, happiness, God (lib. arb. 3.70; div.
qu. 35.2; civ. 10.3; conf. 13.47). Assent is good if it results in moral
behaviour, if desire is directed towards appropriate goals, and for the right
reasons. It is the same with the emotions. They are expressions of the
irrational faculty, and forms of intention. They should be controlled by
reason and used properly. They are an inescapable feature of our
condition: Augustine does not believe in the existence of a dispassionate
soul (civ. 9.4; 14.6–10).
Augustine’s insistence upon the value of introspection, both as a means of
discovering the truth and as a condition of moral purification (vera rel. 72;
trin. 9.4; 10.2–15), leads him to talk of senses of the soul, of inner senses,
inner speaking, and—using a Pauline analogy (Romans 7:22–3, etc.)—of
the ‘inner man’ (ser. 126.3; Io. ev. tr. 99.4; civ. 13.24). Augustine supposes
that such locutions are about our souls or our minds, and that the
phenomena which they describe entail mind-body dualism. But they do
not. They may describe the contrast (or consistency) between model cases
of human behaviour and how we actually behave, or they may refer to
dissembling or insincere behaviour.<sup>41</sup>
In Christological and Trinitarian contexts Augustine speaks of the
concept of a person, whether he is talking about the unity of Christ’s
persona, despite his human and divine natures, or about the relation
between the three persons of the single substance that is the Trinity (trin. 7.
7–11; ep. 137.11; Io. ev. tr. 19.15). Sometimes he equates the person with
the self, as distinct from the emotional or mental powers or activities (trin.
15.42), or as the subject of personal attributes. But his conclusions do not
lead to any concept of personality as distinct from traditional views of
what it is to be human. The distinction between person and substance in
his Trinitarian theology, and the relational aspect of his definition of
person there, are not exploited in his account of human psychology.<sup>42</sup>
8
SENSE-PERCEPTION AND IMAGINATION
Augustine’s theory of sense-perception has a physiological bias. Like
Plotinus, he exploits the discovery of the nervous system by Alexandrian
medicine (Plotinus 4.3.23; see Solmsen [12.106]). The sensory nerves
transmit stimuli to the brain from the various sense-organs. The nerves
contain soul pneuma as a means of communication between brain and
senses (Gn. litt. 7.13.20; 7.19.25). Augustine co-ordinates this belief with
other traditional philosophical accounts of perceptive processes, such as the
ray theory of vision (trin. 9.3; ser. 277.10). The senses are not reflexive,
and awareness of their activity is a perception of the internal sense (which
corresponds to Aristotle’s koinê aisthêsis), which controls and judges
sensations (lib. arb. 2.8–12). Sensation is a form of motion or change.
Augustine believes that it is a motion running counter to the motion set up
in the body by sensory stimuli (mus. 6.10–11, 15). Sentience is the product
of the interaction of two movements of qualitative change. Most likely it is
the soul pneuma that is set in motion in this process. Because of the
presence of pneuma in the sensory nerves, they are themselves sentient. The
perceiving subject, soul, is entirely present in them, and is not merely
located in a central receptive organ with which they communicate in a nonsentient
way (imm. an. 25; c. ep. fund. 16.20).
But if sensation has a physiological mechanism, perception is nonetheless
a psychological process. The body-soul interaction in perception is a kind of
tempering by mixture (contemperatio); its mental aspect is called
concentration (intentio). In vision, for example, the visual ray is the
necessary physical counterpart of mental concentration. Intentio is an
activity, the active concentration of soul power: perception is exercised
upon the sensory stimulus rather than being a passive reception of the
latter (quant. an. 41–9; mus. 6.7–11; trin. 11.2; Gn. litt. 7.20.26; 12.12.
25; 12.20.42). Body does not act upon soul: ‘perception is something
directly undergone by the body of which the soul is aware’ (quant. an. 48).
Augustine extends the notions of concentration and counter-motion to his
accounts of feelings like pleasure and pain (mus. 6.5, 9, 23, 26, 34–58).
The awareness implicit in any perceptive process is underpinned by the
instantaneous operation of memory. A series of memory-impressions is
stored in the mind in the course of even the shortest perception, and this
process is essential to the functioning of perception (mus. 6.21; Gn. litt. 12.
11.22). Some texts of Augustine dispute that perception gives us any
knowledge of the external world, suggesting that there are no
characteristics of our sense-perceptions that enable us infallibly to
distinguish between true and false (c. Acad. 3.39; div. qu. 9). But many
other texts make claims for our ability to know the external world, the
kind of knowledge that Augustine calls scientia, contrasting it with
sapientia, the knowledge of eternal and immutable truths (trin. 12.16–17,
21; 15.21). Even optical illusions have a kind of consistency (c. Acad. 3.
36). Augustine maintains that if our perception of an object is
comprehensive and our faculties are functioning normally, reliable
information may be acquired about the external world (ep. 147.21; civ. 19.
18).
Sense-perception is perception of images of objects, not of the objects
themselves, and these images are not corporeal. Like Aristotle (De anima 2.
12), Augustine argues that perception is the ability to receive forms
without matter (quant. an. 8–9). Moreover, perception is the perception of
like by like. There is an affinity between the percipient’s reason and the
image or form of the object perceived, and it is this affinity which makes
perception possible as well as reliable (ord. 2.32–3; trin. 11.2, 4, 26). Now
the objects of perception are themselves formed by the Forms or Reasons
or Ideas in the mind of God, to which they owe their existence (div. qu. 23,
46). In sense-perception these Forms function as standards (regulae)
accessible to our minds whereby we may distinguish between the truth and
falsity of the images conveyed by perception (vera rel. 58; trin. 9.9–11).
When the mind errs in its evaluation of perceptions it does so because it
applies itself to the phenomena in question in some deficient way: access to
the Forms is no guarantee of infallibility in perception (Gn. litt. 12.25.52).
Assembling of evidence and common sense will prevent mistakes being
made: Augustine believes that we are capable of establishing working
distinctions between reliable and illusory perceptions. Strictly speaking,
perception does not convey certainty, but empirical processes operate on the
basis of a distinction between true and false, and there is a ‘truth appropriate
to this class of things’ (ibid.). That this is so is due to our access to the
transcendent criterion, the Form, because of divine illumination of our
minds (sol. 1.27; trin. 9.10–11).
The reproductive exercise of the imagination (often called phantasia by
Augustine) depends on remembered images that are reactivated, but so
does the creative activity of imagination (often called phantasma by him)
(mus. 6.32; trin. 8.9; 9.10). Imagination may be willed and subject to our
control, but not necessarily so. Creative imagination is a process of
contracting and expanding the images of what we have perceived, or of
combining or separating their data (ep. 7.6; trin. 11.8). In such cases
concentration or will is operative (trin. 11.6–7). But there are imaginative
processes that seem to be involuntary, such as dreams and hallucinations.
Augustine adds to this category prophetic inspiration, arguing that some
dreams are also prophetic. Dreaming is imagining, often on the basis of
images derived from the day’s preoccupations, and it is beyond rational
control (Gn. litt. 12.18.39; 12.23.49; 12.30.58). Thus consent to sinful
actions in dreams is not morally reprehensible although it is the case that
our dreams reflect our moral character (see section 5). In dreams the
creative imagination is more usually in operation. But not all dreams or
visions are entirely dependent upon our mental powers. Augustine
recognizes external agencies, divine, angelic, or demonic, and is curious to
explain a wide variety of paranormal phenomena in terms of the
imagination (O’Daly [12.46] 118–27). In such cases a reciprocal influence
of body and soul upon one another is often discernible (ep. 9.3–4; Gn. litt.
12.13.27; 12.17.37–8).
Anticipation of intended actions is an activity of imagination, as is the
prediction of future events, and both of these processes depend upon
experience and the creative manipulation of images (conf. 10.14; 11.23–4,
26, 30, 36–8; trin. 15.13; Gn. litt. 12.23.40).
Augustine is also interested in the pathology of the imagination, where
some physical disruption of the link between brain and sensory nervous
system occurs. In such cases concentration takes place, but because it
cannot function normally, it generates images in a wholly introspective
way. Or the disturbance may be in the brain itself or in the sense-organ.
The hallucinatory states which ensue have something in common with
dreams (Gn. litt. 12.12.25; 12.20.42–4).
There is no single influence upon Augustine’s accounts of senseperception
and imagination. The Stoic concept of sunaisthêsis lies behind
his definition of perception, as it does behind Plotinus’ account. There are
Neoplatonist traces in his concept of internal sense. But he is not
reproducing other men’s doctrines.<sup>43</sup>
9
MEMORY
Augustine argues that memory is indispensable to our perceptions of
spatiotemporal continua and to the exercise of the imagination. But how
are memory-images formed? The series of images stored in the mind in the
course of every perception is not merely essential to the process of
perception itself, but also to the recollection of perceptions (conf. 10.12–15;
quant. an. 8–9; Gn. litt. 12.16.33). Incorporeal sense-impression leads to
incorporeal memory-image, and memory depends upon and corresponds to
perception in quality, quantity, and kind (trin. 11.13, 16; c. ep. fund. 16.
20). But memory-images are not formed spontaneously. They are willed, a
consequence of concentration. And if memory, like expectation, is a
prerequisite of deliberate action, concentration is the necessary link
between memory and expectation, if the moments of such action are to
cohere (imm. an. 3–4; trin. 11.15).
In his account of the process of remembering Augustine applies the
analogy with sense-perception. The will directs the mind towards the
memory’s contents, and the mind’s vision is formed by memory-images.
Recollecting is perceiving memory-images: it actualizes memory-traces
(mag. 39; trin. 11.6). However, this model of the memory process is only
fully satisfactory as an account of how we remember sense-perceptions,
and, in addition, it only serves as an analogy between types of mental
activity (perceiving and remembering), not between the objects of these
activities. The images perceived in sense-perception are those of objects
actually there and perceptible by other percipients. The truth-value of the
images is verifiable. But Augustine has a difficulty with memory-images of
perceptions, for they are images of things absent, no longer there in the
state in which they were perceived. Augustine suggests that they must have
evidential character as ‘proofs [documenta] of previously perceived things’
(mag. 39), but, strictly speaking, only for the percipient: their verifiability
remains problematic.<sup>44</sup> Augustine does not offer a direct solution to this
dilemma. But elements of his solution may be constructed from his account
of the functional relations between words and images. That he must
envisage a solution is evident, for memory is essential to every type of
knowledge claim, including claims about the objects of sense-perceptions.
What we perceive is an articulated image, a rational structure which has
an affinity with our minds, and is stored in our memory as a form of
knowledge. When we wish to reactivate this knowledge by directing our
concentration upon it, we generate an ‘inner word’, co-extensive with the
memory-image. The image appears to be stored in the memory pre-verbally,
as a word-potential (trin. 8.9; 15.16, 19–22). The linguistic metaphor here
employed, and the reason for its employment, are clarified by Augustine’s
remarks about the understanding and retention of the meaning of words
(dial. 5). The meaning (dicibile) grasped by the mind is also a wordpotential,
capable of being expressed in language. But meaning is always
present to the mind in a verbal manner. Also, it may have a general
semantic function: the meaning of ‘city’, if understood, enables me, not
merely to recall or recognize known cities, but also to identify new cities
and classify them, and so on. Identifying, understanding, naming, and
recalling are inextricably linked. Not every perception must be
accompanied by overt naming of the object perceived, but naming is
usually at least implicit or expected. The metaphor of the ‘inner word’
recognizes this. But Augustine also feels that he can best elucidate the
mechanism of perceiving, storing, and recalling by the linguistic illustration:
grasping a word’s meaning, storing it as a dicibile, and expressing it.
Recalling my memory-image of an object is like actualizing the semantic
content of a known word, it is like bringing its meaning to mind. What this
analogy emphasizes is the coherence and objectivity of our recollected
perceptions: memory claims are meaningful.<sup>45</sup>
Augustine does not apply this solution to the problem of the verifiability
of memory-images. But the implication of his argument is that, if senseperception
leads to knowledge of the external world, memory is the storing
of such knowledge. Verifying memory-claims may involve deciding
whether another person’s claims are worthy of credence on grounds of
inherent plausibility: it involves deciding what I should believe, and for
Augustine belief is a form of knowledge (see section 3).
Augustine extends the mental-image theory to one other type of
memory, that of past emotions, but he does so tentatively (conf. 10.21–3).
For recalling a past feeling need not entail re-experiencing that feeling,
whereas the memory-image of a past perception conveys some distinctive
quality of what is remembered. Augustine adduces his famous metaphor of
memory as the mind’s ‘stomach’ (conf. 10.21), taking in but transforming
different emotions. But he is clearly not at ease with the application of the
mental-image theory to this kind of memory, chiefly because the ideas of
past feelings have not been perceived by any of the senses, but are derived
from the mind’s introspection of its own experiences. However, if he were
to claim that they can be recalled without an image, he would be making a
claim about them that is made for recalled ideal numbers, scientific
principles, and Forms. Affections may be mental phenomena, but we can
recall them only because we have experienced them, unlike numbers,
principles, and Forms. Against the trend of his argument Augustine
concludes that memories of past f feelings are more like memories of past
perceptions than the privileged category of remembering that does not
require images.
Augustine puts forward a criterion for establishing that something is in
the memory. If I can name P and recognize what the name P refers to, I
remember P (conf. 10.23). He applies this criterion to the fact of forgetting
(conf. 10.24–5, 27–8). But how can I actualize forgetting in my mind
without, in fact, forgetting? Augustine first suggests that the image theory
may solve the problem: recalling forgetting may be like recalling a past
feeling, and I must not actually experience forgetting every time I recall it.
But he is not satisfied with this suggestion, and embarks upon an
alternative argument. When I forget the name of a person I know, both my
rejection of wrong names and my recognition of the right name, when I
recall or am told it, are possible only because I have not entirely forgotten
it. Remembering forgetting is related to an object: it is remembering that I
have forgotten something. But to remember that I have forgotten
something entails that I have not entirely forgotten it. And the experience of
forgetting does not entail having a mental image of forgetting. Without
such an image I can recognize what ‘forgetting’ means and so remember
forgetting something. Augustine also suggests that I can recall the
circumstances or context of something which I have forgotten, and that
this can help me recollect it. There may be certain indicators (signa) which
are contextual and remind me by association of what I have forgotten
(trin. 11.12; 14.17).
Memory is the focal point of consciousness, in which past, present, and
future are related: it appears to underwrite the continuity of mental
processes and provide the subject’s sense of his identity (conf. 1.12; 10.14,
21, 26). Mind, memory, and the self are inextricably linked, and Augustine
may seem to argue that my identity is dependent upon continuity of
consciousness, as does Locke (Essay Concerning Human Understanding 2.
27.9). But Augustine is not making any such claim. He points out that
areas of my past, such as infancy, are not accessible to my memory, yet
nonetheless constitute my identity: my knowledge of myself, past and
present, is imperfect (conf. 1.7–12; 2.1; 10.15). Nor is memory the mind
without qualification, but rather the mind engaged in certain activities, just
as understanding and will are the mind engaged in equally distinctive
activities (trin. 10.18–19). Augustine is familiar with the Platonic theory of
recollection (anamnêsis) as an explanation of the presence in the mind of
knowledge that is not derived from sense-experience. He mentions the
complementary doctrine of the soul’s pre-existence as a possibility for the
created human soul (lib. arb. 1.24; 3.56–9), but never adopts the doctrine,
preferring to use Platonic language about recollection to convey active and
latent states of the mind’s possession of knowledge (see section 7).<sup>46</sup>
Recollection is eliciting what is latent in the memory by a process of
mental concentration and ordering (quant. an. 50–6). Because of the
mind’s intelligible nature it is ‘joined…to intelligible object in a natural
arrangement [naturali ordine]’ (trin. 12.24). Such objects are known by
direct acquaintance, and no mental image is required in recollecting them
(conf. 10.16–19).
It might seem appropriate for Augustine to say that God too is in my
memory, like ideas. But he is careful to stress that God cannot be in my
memory before I learn of him. The reason is, that God is both knowable
(as the truth and the Good) and unknowable to the human mind (sol. 1.15;
ord. 2.44, 47; ep. 130.28; Gn. litt. 5.16.34), whereas Forms and scientific
principles are fully known by us. Knowing God is a different matter,
attainable only in a paradoxical sense, and by submission of the will. I may
love God before I know him, but I can only remember God after I have, in
some respect, learnt about him (conf. 10.8–11, 35–8).
Augustine’s use of memoria and of terms f or remembering covers a wide
range of activities, not all of them self-evidently kinds of memory: selfconsciousness,
self-knowledge, understanding a scientific principle. In this
he is influenced by Platonist anamnêsis theory and discussions about the
rediscovery of one’s true self by self-reflection. His account of memory is
recognizably part of ancient philosophical discussions of the problem. But
it is not possible to identify a specific influence to which he is indebted.
He neither agrees with Aristotle that all memory processes depend upon
the mental image, nor with Plotinus that such an image theory is
unnecessary. He implicitly concurs with Stoic theory in his account of
memories of sense-perceptions, and his account owes much to Stoic views
on presentation and assent (SVF 2.83, 115 [7.2]). But he cannot accept the
Stoic theory as a global account of memory. His view that in some kinds of
memory the mental image is a prerequisite, whereas in others it is not, is
closest to Plato’s position, even if it cannot be based on extensive reading
of Plato’s dialogues. Several elements of Augustine’s account are
anticipated in Cicero (Tusculan Disputations 1.57–71): memory as an
impressive power of the immaterial mind, and as a means of understanding
the mind’s self-knowledge and obtaining knowledge of God through his
works and by analogy with the human mind. But if the themes are
traditional, Augustine’s analysis is of sustained originality.<sup>47</sup>
Some uses of memory-language in Augustine appear questionable or
untenable. One such case is his claim that memory is essential to the
performance of serial operations such as perception or speaking a sentence.
These are not cases of actual reminiscence or memory performance. Notforgetting
or bearing in mind are not instances of recalling or
remembering, and the concomitant concentration is neither remembering
nor does it entail self-consciousness in the sense implied by Augustine.<sup>48</sup>
10
TIME
Although Augustine occasionally refers to time as a trace or copy of
eternity (mus. 6.29; en. Ps. 9.17; Gn. litt. imp. 13.38), he departs from the
Platonic tradition in not attempting to analyse time with reference to
eternity (conf. 11.17–39). The contrast between God’s eternity and human
temporality leads Augustine to consider time empirically, as a fact of
everyday experience, a practical problem. The ensuing speculative freedom
of his discussion has attracted much modern attention: for Wittgenstein
(Philosophical Investigations 89–90) it is an example of a typical but
flawed kind of discourse about time.<sup>49</sup>
Augustine’s puzzles about the difficulty of defining something as familiar
as time are traditional in ancient philosophy since Aristotle (Physics 4.10–
14). They lead him not to a definition of time, but to an attempt to answer
two questions: how do we measure time? how can stretches of time have
any length? Augustine admits, if only by implication, that time may not be
explicitly definable. His celebrated description of time as a distentio animi
(conf. 11.33) is not so much a definition as a metaphor evoking the
psychological state (more ‘tension’ or ‘distraction’ than ‘extension’) that
accompanies the mental act of time-measurement.<sup>50</sup>
Augustine believes that time is an infinitely divisible continuum. There
are no time-atoms. There are extended time-stretches, but at any
given instant time has no actual measurable extent (conf. 11.20, 34).
Nevertheless, Augustine erroneously asserts that the present ‘is’ (exists now),
despite being extensionless and without duration (conf. 11.22–6). This is
partly due to the fact that, like most ancient philosophers, he views time as
a flow of events of which each instant successively constitutes a present or
‘now’ (Plutarch, De communibus notitiis 1082A).<sup>51</sup> But heal so assumes
that ‘now’ is a point or part of time, failing to see that the division of an
extended time-stretch will always result in extended time-stretches. For
Augustine, the past and the future do not exist (in the sense of existing now),
but are present in memory and expectation. Past events are present in the
images derived from sense-perception; the presence of the signs or causes of
future events enables us to anticipate or predict them. Like the Stoics (SVF
2.509, 518–19 [7.2]), Augustine criticizes conventional language
concerning three grammatical tenses: we should, strictly speaking, talk only
of three present tenses, and of a ‘present of things past’ and a ‘present of
things future’ (conf. 11.22–4, 26).
Time is measured in the mind, and is a measurement of duration, which
may be a duration of change or motion, but need not be so. Augustine is at
pains to demonstrate that our ability to make temporal measurements is
prior to, and independent of, any observed physical movement. Time units
like day and year are indeed derived from observation of the motion of
heavenly bodies, which form an astronomical clock, but our time sense
does not presuppose a clock, depending rather upon memories of timestretches.
When the sun stood still in Joshua’s war against the Amorites
(Joshua 10: 12–13), time qua, duration still passed (conf. 11.27, 29–30).
Time is the measurement of a relation, by comparison with known
(remembered) time-stretches, but we do not make direct temporal
comparisons with the standard unit of measurement: measuring time is not
like measuring length, for example. Nor do we measure time as it passes,
for time at any given instant is extensionless. What we measure is not the
time-process itself, but the impress (affectio) which memory retains after
perceptions. In the case of future processes, we measure them by
anticipation when we possess the necessary knowledge to enable us to
make advance calculations (conf. 11.31, 33–8).
Augustine’s insight that our ability to measure times depends upon the
fact that durations can be remembered is vitiated by his inference that the
time-impress (affectio) is the time-stretch itself. He is led to the inference
because he believes that when a time is not present it does not exist, and
that the past and the future must somehow currently exist, if they are to be
the objects of currently existing memory or expectation. But the proper
objects of present memories and expectations are past and future events
(not times), and it is they which do not have present existence. Yet that fact
does not entail that my dealing with them can take place only through
present images and signs of them.<sup>52</sup> Elements of Augustine’s analysis of timemeasurement
reflect Stoic views: the assumption that time is infinitely
divisible; the distinction between loose and strict language about temporal
phenomena, especially the criticism of grammatical tenses; the distinction
between infinite duration and least perceptible times. It is likely that his
analysis develops from a Stoic or Stoic-influenced discussion. But his
conclusions form a personal contribution of great ingenuity to traditional
questions.<sup>53</sup>
Augustine believes that there cannot be time before the creation, for time
requires change and there was no change in God’s eternity. Time,
therefore, had a beginning (conf. 11.12–16; civ. 11.6; Gn. litt. 5.5.12). The
principle that time requires change is common to Plato, Aristotle, and the
Stoics, but Augustine appears to repudiate it when he argues for the
primacy of time sense over measured time units. Perhaps he should have
concentrated upon the argument that, since creation is a first event, there
cannot be time before that event.<sup>54</sup>
11
GOD AND CREATION
Augustine’s concept of divine immutability developed gradually. Initially he
seems to have accepted the Manichaean belief that there is a changeable
divine principle partly immanent in nature. Later he thought of God as
immanent and material, but infinite, incorruptible and immutable. His
encounter with the Platonists changed his concept of God definitively: God
is transcendent, immaterial, and his timelessness entails unchangeability
(duab. an. 16; vera rel. 16; conf. 7.1–2, 26; en. Ps. 101). God is subject
neither to decay nor death, he is perfect living being, in whom substance
and qualities are identical (trin. 6.6, 8; 7.1–3).
The ‘present’ of God’s existence is extensionless, like the ‘present’ of an
infinitely divisible time continuum, but God’s present is indivisible, a
condition of permanent stability (vera rel. 97; conf. 11.12; ser. 6.4). Divine
substance is mental: the eternal Forms (rationes, ideae) are, in Middle
Platonist fashion, understood to be in the divine mind, and the second
person of the Trinity is often said to be divine wisdom or truth, and hence
God is truth (div. qu. 46.2; mag. 38; trin. 4.3). Divine perfection is perfect
life, thought, and will (conf. 3.10; div. qu. 28).
God is omniscient. His knowledge necessarily embraces events in time,
but he does not and cannot know these as past and future occurrences.
God apprehends temporal events timelessly as present events. It is more
correct to say that he has knowledge, rather than foreknowledge, of events
that have not yet happened, and this knowledge is immutable (civ. 5.9; 11.
21; Simpl. 2.2.2).<sup>55</sup> Although Augustine does not apply this notion of
God’s not knowing the future as future to the question whether divine
foreknowledge entails determinism, he in fact argues that divine
foreknowledge is compatible with free choice of the will (lib. arb. 3.4–9).
God the creator timelessly causes the universe to begin. The ‘Why not
sooner?’ argument against its beginning is countered by Augustine’s
insistence that there was no time before the creation, since time depends on
change and God is unchanging. Nor does creation entail that God’s will
changes: he changelessly wills to create the universe. The notions that the
universe persists for ever or that worlds endlessly recur derive from the
misconception that there is otherwise a time prior to creation in which God
is idle (conf. 11.8, 12–17; 12.18, 38; civ. 11.4–6, 21; 12.15, 18).<sup>56</sup>
The Greek philosophical principle that nothing comes from nothing led
some authors in the Judaeo-Christian tradition to assert that God made the
world out of a pre-existing, beginningless matter. But others violated the
principle by asserting that God created the world out of nothing.<sup>57</sup>
Augustine adopts the latter viewpoint, which had become dominant by his
day (Gn. litt. imp. 1.2; sol. 1.2; mus. 6.57; conf. 11.7; 12.7; 13.48; vera
rel. 35; c. Fel. 2.19). But he also argues that God creates unformed matter
from nothing, to be the subject of change. Matter is the necessary condition
of change, but its creation does not precede that of created beings. Even
created immaterial beings have a ‘spiritual’ matter (conf. 12.4–8, 38; Gn.
litt. 1.4.9–5.11; 5.5.12–16; 7.6.9–9.12; Gn. litt. imp. 4.11–15; Armstrong
[12.117]).
Creation is instantaneous and complete, but living organisms are
produced at different times throughout the history of the world. In order to
account both for the completeness of creation at the moment of creation
and the gradual realization of created organisms Augustine adopts and
adapts the theory of seminal logoi (rationes causales, seminales). These are
immaterial causes and conditions of living organisms, potentials that are
realized in the material seeds from which plants and animals develop, with
all their specific differences. The rationes are created in the primal creation,
along with the heavenly bodies, the firmament, and the elements of earth
and water (Gn. litt. 5–7; trin. 3.13, 16).<sup>58</sup>
ABBREVIATIONS
b. coniug. De bono coniugali
beata v. De beata vita
c. Acad. Contra Academicos
c. ep. fund. Contra epistulam fundamenti
c. ep. Pel. Contra duas epistulas Pelagianorum
c. Faust. Contra Faustum Manichaeum
c. Fel. Contra Felicem
c. Iul. Contra Iulianum Pelagianum
c. Iul. imp. Contra Iulianum opus imperfectum
civ. De civitate Dei
conf. Confessiones
corrept. De correptione et gratia
dial. De dialectica
div. qu. De diversis quaestionibus LXXXIII
doctr. chr. De doctrina christiana
duab. an. De duabus animabus
ench. Enchiridion ad Laurentium
en. Ps. Enarrationes in Psalmos
ep. Epistulae
Gn. c. Man. De Genesi contra Manichaeos
Gn. litt. De Genesi ad litteram
Gn. litt. imp. De Genesi ad litteram imperfectus liber
gr. et. lib. arb. De gratia et libero arbitrio
gr. et pecc. or. De gratia Christi et de peccato originali
imm. an. De immortalitate animae
Io. ev. tr. Tractatus in Evangelium Iohannis
lib. arb. De libero arbitrio
mag. De magistro
mor. De moribus ecclesiae catholicae et de moribus
Manichaeorum
mus. De musica
ord. De ordine
pecc. mer. De peccatorum meritis et remissione
praed. sanct. De praedestinatione sanctorum
quant. an. De quantitate animae
retr. Retractationes
ser. Sermones
Simpl. De diversis quaestionibus ad Simplicianum
sol. Soliloquia
spir. et litt. De spiritu et littera
trin. De trinitate
util. cred. De utilitate credendi
vera rel. De vera religione
NOTES
1 Hagendahl [12.57] 79–94, 486–97.
2 Hagendahl [12.57] 52–156, 498–553.
3 Courcelle [12.56] 159–76; O’Meara [12.38] 131–55.
4 Marrou [12.59] 27–46; Courcelle [12.56] 183–94.
5 Fredriksen [12.51]; Markus [12.52].
6 Miles [12.88] 99–125.
7 O’Daly [12.46] 7–79.
8 Kretzmann [12.64].
9 Rist [12.48] 41–8, 53–6.
10 Kirwan [12.42] 22.
11 Kirwan [12.42] 22–3.
12 Matthews [12.69]; Kirwan [12.42] 30–4; Sorabji [12.120] 289; Rist [12.48]
63–7.
13 Letter to Colvius, Adam-Tannery 3.247; Philosophical Letters, tr. A.Kenny,
Oxford 1970, 83–4; Matthews [12.70] 11–38.
14 O’Daly [12.104]; cf. O’Connell [12.102].
15 Nash [12.71] 94–124; O’Daly [12.46] 203–7.
16 O’Donovan [12.47] 60–92.
17 Rist [12.48] 23–40.
18 Stock [12.77] 138–45.
19 Kirwan [12.42] 55–9.
20 Stock [12.77] 145–62.
21 Markus [12.73]; Mayer [12.75].
22 Rist [12.48] 48–53.
23 O’Donovan [12.89].
24 Kirwan [12.42] 187–92.
25 Rist [12.98].
26 Dihle [12.81].
27 Deane [12.80] 78–94.
28 Rist [12.48] 203–55.
29 Deane [12.80] 94–153; Markus [12.85] 72–104.
30 Brown [12.79] 387–427.
31 Matthews [12.70] 90–106; Kirwan [12.42] 192–6.
32 Markus [12.86]; Swift [12.92].
33 Kirwan [12.42] 204–8.
34 Harrison [12.83]; Svoboda [12.91].
35 Rist [12.48] 148–202.
36 Kirwan [12.42] 78–81.
37 O’Daly [12.96] 93–7; Kirwan [12.42] 82–150.
38 O’Daly [12.46] 8–11.
39 O’Daly [12.105].
40 O’Daly [12.46] 62–70.
41 Matthews [12.101].
42 Lloyd [12.100], criticizing Henry [12.99],
43 Schwyzer [12.60]; O’Daly [12.46] 103–4.
44 Matthews [12.110]; Bubacz [12.109].
45 O’Daly [12.46] 141–5.
46 O’Daly [12.104]; O’Connell [12.103].
47 O’Daly [12.112] 44–6.
48 G.Ryle, The Concept of Mind, London, Hutchinson’s University Library,
1949, 6.4.
49 Mundle [12.115]; McEvoy [12.114].
50 O’Daly [12.116].
51 Sorabji [12.120] 35–51.
52 Kirwan [12.42] 182–3.
53 O’Daly [12.46] 153–9; Rist [12.48] 73–85.
54 Sorabji [12.120] 232–8; Kirwan [12.42] 163–6.
55 Sorabji [12.120] 255–6, 263–4; Kirwan [12.42] 171–4.
56 Sorabji [12.120] 232–8; Kirwan [12.42] 159–63.
57 Sorabji [12.120] 193–202; May [12.118] 122–82.
58 TeSelle [12.49] 216–18; Meyer [12.119].
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Note: A full synopsis of Augustine’s works and of modern editions is
provided in [12.30] 1.xxvi–xli.
ORIGINAL LANGUAGE EDITIONS
12.1 Sancti Augustini Hipponensis Episcopi Opera Omnia, ed. J.-P.Migne, Paris,
11 vols, 1841–2 (=Patrologia Latina 32–47). A reprint of the Benedictine
edition of St Maur, Paris, 1679–1700.
12.2 Corpus Scriptorum Ecclesiasticorum Latinorum, Vienna, Hoelder-Pichler-
Tempsky, 1866–. Several vols devoted to Augustine (in progress).
12.3 Corpus Christianorum. Series Latina, Turnhout, Brepols, 1953–. Several vols
devoted to Augustine (in progress).
12.4 Bibliothèque Augustinienne. Oeuvres de Saint Augustin, Paris, Desclée de
Brouwer and Etudes Augustiniennes, 1936–. In progress. With French trans.,
introductions, and notes.
12.5 S.Aureli Augustini Confessionum libri XIII, ed. M.Skutella. Stuttgart, B.G.
Teubner, 2nd edn, 1969.
12.6 Sancti Aurelii Augustini Episcopi De Civitate Dei libri XXII, ed. B.Dombart
and A.Kalb.Leipzig, B.G.Teubner, 4th edn, 1928–9.
12.7 Augustine, De Dialectica, ed. B.Darrell Jackson and J.Pinborg. Dordrecht/
Boston, Mass., North-Holland Publishing, 1975.
ENGLISH TRANSLATIONS
12.8 The Works of Aurelius Augustine, Bishop of Hippo, ed. M.Dods. Edinburgh,
T. and T.Clark, 15 vols, 1871–6. Wide selection of Augustine’s works.
12.9 A Select Library of the Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers of the Christian
Church, New York, 1887–1902. Wide selection of Augustine’s works
(reprinted by W.B.Eerdmans, Grand Rapids, Mich., 1979: vols 1–8=
Augustine).
12.10 Ancient Christian Writers, Westminster, Maryland (later New York),
Newman Press, 1946–. Several vols devoted to Augustine (in progress).
12.11 The Fathers of the Church, Washington DC, Catholic University of America
Press, 1947–. Several vols devoted to Augustine (in progress).
12.12 V.J.Bourke (ed.), The Essential Augustine, selection with commentary,
Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Co., 1974.
12.13 Augustine: Confessions, trans. H.Chadwick. Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 1991.
12.14 Augustine: City of God, trans. H.Bettenson. Harmondsworth, Penguin
Books, new edn 1984.
12.15 Saint Augustine: On Free Choice of the Will, trans. A.S.Benjamin and L.H.
Hackstaff. Indianapolis/New York, Bobbs-Merrill, 1964.
12.16 Saint Augustine: On Christian Teaching, tr. R.Green, with introduction and
notes. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1997.
COMMENTARIES
12.17 J.J.O’Meara (ed.), St. Augustine: Against the Academics, Ancient Christian
Writers, vol. 12 (see [12.10] above), 1951.
12.18 T.Fuhrer (ed.), Angustin: Contra Academicos (vel De Academicis) Bücher 2
und 3, Patristische Texte und Studien, 46. Berlin and New York, de Gruyter,
1997.
12.19 J.J.O’Donnell (ed.), Augustine: Confessions, introduction, text, commentary.
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 3 vols, 1992.
12.20 G.Clark (ed.), Augustine: Confessions I–IV. Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1995.
12.21 E.P.Meijering (ed.), Augustin über Schöpfung, Ewigkeit und Zeit. Das elfte
Buch der Bekenntnisse, Philosophia Patrum, 4. Leiden, E.J.Brill, 1979.
12.22 G.Watson (ed.), Augustine: Soliloquies and Immortality of the Soul.
Warminster, Aris and Phillips, 1991.
12.23 P.Agaësse and A.Solignac (eds), De Genesi ad Litteram, Bibliothèque
Augustinienne, vols 48–9 (see [12.4] above), 1972.
See also [12.7] and the notes in the individual vols of [12.4].
BIBLIOGRAPHIES AND RESEARCH REPORTS
12.24 C.Andresen, Bibliographia Augustiniana. Darmstadt, Wissenschaftliche
Buchgesellschaft, 2nd edn, 1973.
12.25 T.J.van Bavel and F.van der Zande, Repertoire bibliographique de saint
Augustin 1950–1960. Stenbrugge/Den Haag, M.Nijhoff, 1963.
12.26 R.Lorenz, ‘Augustinliteratur seit dem Jubiläum von 1954’, Theologische
Rundschau NF 25 (1959) 1–75; id., ‘Zwölf Jahre Augustinusforschung
(1959–1970)’, Theologische Rundschau NF 38 (1974) 292–333; 39 (1974)
95–138, 253–86, 331–64; 40 (1975) 1–41, 97–149, 227–61.
12.27 Augustine Bibliography/Fichier Augustinien, Boston, Mass., G.K.Hall, 4 vols,
1972. Supplementary vol. 1981.
12.28 Revue des Etudes Augustiniennes (1955–) incorporates an annual
bibliographical survey (Bulletin).
CONCORDANCE
12.29 Corpus Augustinianum Gissense, ed. C.Mayer. Computerized concordance
of all of Augustine’s writings and bibliography on CD-ROM. Basle,
Schwabe, 1996.
ENCYCLOPAEDIA
12.30 C.Mayer et al., Augustinus-Lexikon. Basle, Schwabe, 1986– .
BIOGRAPHIES AND GENERAL SURVEYS
Ancient
12.31 (Possidius) M.Pellegrino (ed.), Possidio, Vita di S. Agostino, Alba, Edizioni
Paoline, 1955.
Modern
12.32 G.Bonner, St Augustine of Hippo: Life and Controversies, Norwich,
Canterbury Press, 2nd edn, 1986.
12.33 P.Brown, Augustine of Hippo: A Biography, London, Faber & Faber, 1967.
12.34 J.Burnaby, Amor Dei: A Study of the Religion of St Augustine, London,
Hodder & Stoughton, 1938 (reprinted Norwich, Canterbury Press, 1991).
12.35 H.Chadwick, Augustine, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1986.
12.36 C.Horn, Augustinus, Munich, C.H.Beck, 1995.
12.37 J.J.O’Donnell, Augustine, Boston, Mass., Twayne Publishers, 1985.
12.38 J.J.O’Meara, The Young Augustine: The Growth of St Augustine’s Mind up
to his Conversion, London, Longmans, Green, 1954.
12.39 A.Schindler, ‘Augustin’, Theologische Realenzyklopädie 4 (1979) 646–98.
AUGUSTINE’S PHILOSOPHY: GENERAL STUDIES, COLLECTIONS OF ARTICLES
12.40 G.R.Evans, Augustine on Evil, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1982.
12.41 E.Gilson, Introduction a l’étude de Saint Augustin, Paris, J.Vrin, 4th edn,
1969 (Eng. trans. of 1st edn, The Christian Philosophy of Saint Augustine,
New York, Random House, 1960).
12.42 C.Kirwan, Augustine, London and New York, Routledge, 1989.
12.43 R.A.Markus, in A.H.Armstrong (ed.), The Cambridge History of Later
Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1967, 341–419.
12.44 R.A.Markus (ed.), Augustine: A Collection of Critical Essays, New York,
Doubleday, 1972.
12.45 R.J.O’Connell, St Augustine’s Early Theory of Man, A.D. 386–391,
Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1968.
12.46 G.O’Daly, Augustine’s Philosophy of Mind, London, Duckworth, 1987.
12.47 O.O’Donovan, The Problem of Self-Love in St Augustine, New Haven/
London, Yale University Press, 1980.
12.48 J.M.Rist, Augustine: Ancient Thought Baptized, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1994.
12.49 E.TeSelle, Augustine the Theologian, London, Burns & Oates, 1970.
AUGUSTINE AS AUTOBIOGRAPHER
12.50 G.Clark, Augustine: The Confessions, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1993.
12.51 P.Fredriksen, ‘Paul and Augustine: Conversion Narratives, Orthodox
Traditions, and the Retrospective Self’, Journal of Theological Studies NS 37
(1986) 3–34.
12.52 R.A.Markus, Conversion and Disenchantment in Augustine’s Spiritual
Career, Villanova, Pa., Villanova University Press, 1989.
12.53 G.Misch, A History of Autobiography in Antiquity, London, Routledge and
Kegan Paul, vol. 2, 1950, 625–67.
AUGUSTINE’S PHILOSOPHICAL READINGS
12.54 A.H.Armstrong, ‘St Augustine and Christian Platonism’, in [12.44] 3–37.
12.55 M.Colish, The Stoic Tradition from Antiquity to the Early Middle Ages,
Leiden, E.J.Brill, vol. 2, 1985.
12.56 P.Courcelle, Les Lettres grecques en Occident de Macrobe a Cassiodore,
Paris, Boccard, 2nd edn, 1948 (Eng. trans. Late Latin Writers and their
Greek Sources, Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1969).
12.57 H.Hagendahl, Augustine and the Latin Classics, Göteborg, Institute of
Classical Studies of the University of Göteborg, 2 vols, 1967.
12.58 P.Henry, Plotin et l’Occident: Firmicus Maternus, Marius Victorinus, Saint
Augustin et Macrobe, Louvain, Spicilegium Sacrum Lovaniense, 1934.
12.59 H.-I.Marrou, Saint Augustin et la fin de la culture antique, Paris, Boccard,
1938, and Retractatio, Paris, Boccard, 1949.
12.60 H.-R.Schwyzer, ‘Bewußt und Unbewußt bei Plotin’, Les Sources de Plotin,
Entretiens Fondation Hardt, 5, Vandoeuvres/Geneva, 1960, 343–90.
12.61 A.Solignac, ‘Doxographies et manuels dans la formation philosophique de s.
Augustin’, Recherches Augustiniennes 1 (1958) 113–48.
12.62 M.Testard, Saint Augustin et Cicéron, Paris, Etudes Augustiniennes, 2 vols,
1958.
12.63 W.Theiler, ‘Porphyrios und Augustin’, Forschungen zum Neuplatonismus,
Berlin, de Gruyter, 1966, 160–251 (first published 1933).
AUGUSTINE’S CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY
12.64 N.Kretzmann, ‘Faith Seeks, Understanding Finds: Augustine’s Charter for
Christian Philosophy’, in T.P.Flint (ed.), Christian Philosophy, Notre Dame,
Ind., University of Notre Dame Press, 1990, 1–36.
12.65 G.Madec, ‘Augustinus’, in ‘Philosophie’, Historisches Wörterbuch der
Philosophie 7 (1989) 630–3.
BELIEF AND KNOWLEDGE
12.66 B.Bubacz, St Augustine’s Theory of Knowledge: A Contemporary Analysis,
New York/Toronto, Edwin Mellen, 1981.
12.67 M.F.Burnyeat, ‘Wittgenstein and Augustine De Magistro’, The Aristotelian
Society. Supplementary Volume 61 (1987) 1–24.
12.68 R.Lorenz, ‘Gnade und Erkenntnis bei Augustinus’, Zeitschrift für
Kirchengeschichte 75 (1964) 21–78.
12.69 G.B.Matthews, ‘Si Fallor Sum’, in [12.44] 151–67.
12.70 G.B.Matthews, Thought’s Ego in Augustine and Descartes, Ithaca, NY and
London, Cornell University Press, 1992.
12.71 R.H.Nash, The Light of the Mind: St Augustine’s Theory of Knowledge,
Lexington, University of Kentucky Press, 1969.
See also [12.46] 162–216; [12.48] 41–91.
SEMANTICS AND HERMENEUTICS
12.72 B.D.Jackson, ‘The Theory of Signs in St Augustine’s De Doctrina Christiana,
in A.H.Armstrong (ed.), The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early
Medieval Philosophy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1967, 92–147
(reprinted from Revue des Etudes Augustiniennes 15 (1969) 9–49). And in
[12.44].
12.73 R.A.Markus, ‘St Augustine on Signs’, in [12.44] 61–91 (reprinted from
Phronesis 2 (1957) 60–83).
12.74 R.A.Markus, Signs and Meanings: World and Text in Ancient Christianity,
Liverpool, Liverpool University Press, 1996.
12.75 C.P.Mayer, Die Zeichen in der geistigen Entwicklung und in der Theologie
Augustins, Würzburg, Augustinus-Verlag, 2 vols, 1969 and 1974.
12.76 K.Pollmann, Doctrina Christiana. Untersuchungen zu den Anfängen der
christlichen Hermeneutik unter besonderer Berücksichtigung von Augustinus,
De doctrina christiana, Paradosis, 41, Fribourg, Universitätsverlag Freiburg
Schweiz, 1996.
12.77 B.Stock, Augustine the Reader: Meditation, Self-Knowledge, and the Ethics
of Interpretation, Cambridge, Mass. and London, Harvard University Press,
1996.
12.78 G.Watson, ‘St Augustine’s Theory of Language’, Maynooth Review 6 (1982)
4–20.
See also [12.48] 23–40.
ETHICS, POLITICAL THEORY, AESTHETICS
12.79 P.Brown, The Body and Society, London, Faber & Faber, 1989, 387–427.
12.80 H.A.Deane, The Political and Social Ideas of St Augustine, New York and
London, Columbia University Press, 1963.
12.81 A.Dihle, Die Goldene Regel, Göttingen, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1962.
12.82 D.F.Donnelly (ed.), The City of God: A Collection of Critical Essays, New
York, Peter Lang, 1995.
12.83 C.Harrison, Beauty and Revelation in the Thought of Saint Augustine,
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1992.
12.84 R.Holte, Béatitude et Sagesse: Saint Augustin et le problème de la fin de
l’homme dans la philosophie ancienne, Paris and Worcester, Mass., Etudes
Augustiniennes and Augustinian Studies, 1962.
12.85 R.A.Markus, Saeculum: History and Society in the Theology of St Augustine,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, revised edn, 1988.
12.86 R.A.Markus, ‘Saint Augustine’s Views on the “Just War”’, Studies in Church
History 20 (1983) 1–13.
12.87 J.Mausbach, Die Ethik des heiligen Augustinus, Freiburg im Breisgau,
Herder, 2 vols, 2nd edn, 1929.
12.88 M.R.Miles, Augustine on the Body, Missoula, Scholars Press, 1979.
12.89 O.O’Donovan, ‘Usus and Fruitio in Augustine, De Doctrina Christiana I’,
Journal of Theological Studies NS 33 (1982) 361–97.
12.90 O.O’Donovan, ‘Augustine’s City of God XIX and Western Political
Thought’, Dionysius 11 (1987) 89–110.
12.91 K.Svoboda, L’Esthétique de S. Augustin et ses sources, Paris/Brno,
Philosophical Faculty of Masaryk, University of Brno, 1933.
12.92 L.J.Swift, ‘Augustine on War and Killing: Another View’, Harvard
Theological Review 66 (1973) 369–83.
12.93 J.Wetzel, Augustine and the Limits of Virtue, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1992.
See also [12.48] 203–55.
WILL
12.94 J.P.Burns, The Development of Augustine’s Doctrine of Operative Grace,
Paris, Etudes Augustiniennes, 1990.
12.95 A.Dihle, The Theory of Will in Classical Antiquity, Berkeley/Los Angeles/
London, University of California Press, 1982.
12.96 G.O’Daly, ‘Predestination and Freedom in Augustine’s Ethics’, in G.Vesey
(ed.), The Philosophy in Christianity, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1989, 85–97.
12.97 J.M.Rist, ‘Augustine on Free Will and Predestination’, Journal of Theological
Studies NS 20 (1969) 420–47.
12.98 J.M.Rist, ‘Plotinus and Augustine on Evil’, Plotino e il Neoplatonismo in
Oriente e in Occidente, Rome, Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei, 1974, 495–
508.
See also [12.48] 148–202; [12.93].
SOUL
12.99 P.Henry, Saint Augustine on Personality, New York, Macmillan, 1960.
12.100 A.C.Lloyd, ‘On Augustine’s Concept of a Person’, in [12.44] 191–205.
12.101 G.B.Matthews, ‘The Inner Man’, in [12.44] 176–90 (reprinted from
American Philosophical Quarterly 4/2 (1967) 1–7).
12.102 R.J.O’Connell, ‘Pre-existence in the Early Augustine’, Revue des Etudes
Augustiniennes 26 (1980) 176–88.
12.103 R.J.O’Connell, The Origin of the Soul in St Augustine’s Later Works, New
York, Fordham University Press, 1988.
12.104 G.O’Daly, ‘Did St Augustine ever believe in the Soul’s Pre-existence?’,
Augustinian Studies 5 (1974) 227–35.
12.105 G.O’Daly, ‘Augustine on the Origin of Souls’, in H.-D.Blume and F.Mann
(eds), Platonismus und Christentum=Jahrbuch für Antike und Christentum,
Ergänzungsband 10 (1983) 184–91.
See also [12.48] 92–147.
SENSE-PERCEPTION AND IMAGINATION
12.106 F.Solmsen, ‘Greek Philosophy and the Discovery of the Nerves’, Museum
Helveticum 18 (1961) 150–67 and 169–97 (reprinted in Kleine Schriften,
Hildesheim, Georg Olms Verlag, vol. 1, 536–82.
12.107 G.Verbeke, L’Évolution de la doctrine du pneuma du Stoicisme a S. Augustin,
Paris/Louvain, Desclée de Brouwer, 1945.
12.108 G.Watson, Phantasia in Classical Thought, Galway, Galway University
Press, 1988.
MEMORY
12.109 B.Bubacz, ‘Augustine’s Account of Factual Memory’, Augustinian Studies 6
(1975) 181–92.
12.110 G.B.Matthews, ‘Augustine on Speaking from Memory’, in [12.44] 168–75
(reprinted from American Philosophical Quarterly 2/2 (1965) 1–4).
12.111 J.A.Mourant, Saint Augustine on Memory, Villanova, Pa., Villanova
University Press, 1980.
12.112 G.O’Daly, ‘Remembering and Forgetting in Augustine, Confessions X’, in
Memoria. Vergessen und Erinnern=Poetik und Hermeneutik XV, Munich,
Wilhelm Fink Verlag, 1993, 31–46.
TIME
12.113 H.M.Lacey, ‘Empiricism and Augustine’s Problems about Time’, in [12.44]
280–308 (reprinted from Review of Metaphysics 22 (1968) 219–45).
12.114 J.McEvoy, ‘St Augustine’s Account of Time and Wittgenstein’s Criticisms’,
Review of Metaphysics 38 (1984) 547–77.
12.115 C.W.K.Mundle, ‘Augustine’s Pervasive Error concerning Time’, Philosophy
41 (1966) 165–8.
12.116 G.O’Daly, ‘Time as distentio and St Augustine’s Exegesis of Philippians 3,
12–14’, Revue des Etudes Augustiniennes 23 (1977) 265–71.
GOD AND CREATION
12.117 A.H.Armstrong, ‘Spiritual or Intelligible Matter in Plotinus and St
Augustine’, Augustinus Magister, Paris, Etudes Augustiniennes, vol. 1, 1954,
277–83.
12.118 G.May, Schöpfung aus dem Nichts, Berlin, de Gruyter, 1978.
12.119 H.Meyer, Geschichte der Lehre von den Keimkräften von der Stoa bis zum
Ausgang der Patristik, Bonn, Peter Hansteins Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1914,
123–224.
12.120 R.Sorabji, Time, Creation and the Continuum: Theories in Antiquity and the
Early Middle Ages, London, Duckworth, 1983.
Routledge History of Philosophy.
Taylor & Francis e-Library.
2005.